Is Ross' paradox really a paradox?












7















Consider the following disjunction introduction:




  1. Your room is clean.

  2. Therefore, your room is clean or your house is burnt down.


Ross' paradox allegedly arises when applying this inference to imperative logic:




  1. Clean your room.

  2. Therefore, clean your room or burn your house down.


Intuitively, 2 doesn't appear to follow from 1. However, it seems to me that this is just due to a syntactic ambiguity in the conclusion. That is, the conclusion could be interpreted in one of two ways:




  1. You should (clean your room or burn your house down).

  2. (You should clean your room) or (you should burn your house down).


The conclusion that follows from "clean your room" is really 2, not 1. Thus I don't see where the paradox arises. More generally, consider a do operator, so that do(x) denotes "x is obligatory" or "I command you to do x". Then the inference





  1. do(x)

  2. Therefore, do(x) or do(y)


is valid but the inference





  1. do(x)

  2. Therefore, do(x or y)


is not. Am I missing something about this purported paradox?



EDIT: Is the underlying problem here the implicit assumption that





  1. do(x)

  2. x → y

  3. Therefore, do(y)


is a valid inference? If so, that doesn't seem right. To see why it's not true in general, consider replacing the do operator with the negation operator:




  1. not(x)

  2. x → y

  3. Therefore, not(y)


This would be a basic formal fallacy called denying the antecedent. It's not true for the modal necessity operator either:




  1. Necessarily, 1 + 1 = 2.

  2. 1 + 1 = 2 → Alexander invaded Persia.

  3. Therefore, necessarily, Alexander invaded Persia.


EDIT 2:



On second thought, I've been thinking about Ross' paradox the wrong way. First, define the following deontic operators:




  • it is obligatory that (OB)

  • it is impermissible that (IM)

  • it is omissible that (OM)

  • it is permissible that (PE)

  • it is optional that (OP)


All of these operators can be expressed in terms of OB alone:




  • IM p ↔ OB ~ p

  • OM p ↔ ~ OB p

  • PE p ↔ ~ OB ~ p

  • OP p ↔ (~ OB p) ∧ (~ OB ~ p)


Consider the simple example:




  1. Mail the letter.

  2. Therefore, mail the letter or burn it.


More formally,




  1. OB (mail the letter)

  2. OB (mail the letter ∨ burn the letter)


I don't see anything wrong with 2 anymore, because it's not really presenting a choice! It's not saying that burning the letter is permissible! Just because an obligation entails a second obligation that would be satisfied by an action, it doesn't mean that the first obligation would be satisfied by that action. If you burn the letter, you would have fulfilled a different obligation entailed by the original obligation, but not the original obligation itself. In fact, doing so would make it impossible to fulfill the original obligation of mailing the letter. Thus burning the letter is impermissible, even though mailing the letter or burning it is permissible (and in fact obligatory)!




  1. burn the letter → ~(mail the letter)

  2. mail the letter → ~(burn the letter) [from 1 by contraposition]

  3. OB(mail the letter) → OB(~(burn the letter)) [from 2 by axiom OB-RM]

  4. OB(mail the letter)

  5. OB(~(burn the letter)) [from 3 and 4 by modus ponens]

  6. IM(burn the letter) [from 5 and the definition of IM]


The key point here is that OB (p ∨ q) is perfectly consistent with IM q, because it's not actually expressing a real choice. But how do you express a real choice then, like "pay up or leave" in the context of a restaurant? The proper way to express a real choice between p and q is not



OB (p ∨ q)



but



OB (p ∨ q) ∧ OP p ∧ OP q



In particular, you must specify that p and q are each optional, lest it turns out that one of them was actually obligatory (or impermissible) individually.










share|improve this question

























  • It doesn't mean burn your house down is valid, it means clean your room or burn your house down is valid since at least one of these is true.

    – EternalPropagation
    Dec 6 '18 at 4:22






  • 1





    @EternalPropagation So what's the paradox?

    – user76284
    Dec 6 '18 at 4:26






  • 1





    Paradoxes don't exist.

    – EternalPropagation
    Dec 6 '18 at 4:26






  • 2





    @EternalPropagation Not helpful. I'm asking why it's called a paradox.

    – user76284
    Dec 6 '18 at 4:33













  • "Clean your room" does not seem like a truth bearer; that is, a sentence that could be true or false and nothing else.

    – user4894
    Dec 6 '18 at 7:01
















7















Consider the following disjunction introduction:




  1. Your room is clean.

  2. Therefore, your room is clean or your house is burnt down.


Ross' paradox allegedly arises when applying this inference to imperative logic:




  1. Clean your room.

  2. Therefore, clean your room or burn your house down.


Intuitively, 2 doesn't appear to follow from 1. However, it seems to me that this is just due to a syntactic ambiguity in the conclusion. That is, the conclusion could be interpreted in one of two ways:




  1. You should (clean your room or burn your house down).

  2. (You should clean your room) or (you should burn your house down).


The conclusion that follows from "clean your room" is really 2, not 1. Thus I don't see where the paradox arises. More generally, consider a do operator, so that do(x) denotes "x is obligatory" or "I command you to do x". Then the inference





  1. do(x)

  2. Therefore, do(x) or do(y)


is valid but the inference





  1. do(x)

  2. Therefore, do(x or y)


is not. Am I missing something about this purported paradox?



EDIT: Is the underlying problem here the implicit assumption that





  1. do(x)

  2. x → y

  3. Therefore, do(y)


is a valid inference? If so, that doesn't seem right. To see why it's not true in general, consider replacing the do operator with the negation operator:




  1. not(x)

  2. x → y

  3. Therefore, not(y)


This would be a basic formal fallacy called denying the antecedent. It's not true for the modal necessity operator either:




  1. Necessarily, 1 + 1 = 2.

  2. 1 + 1 = 2 → Alexander invaded Persia.

  3. Therefore, necessarily, Alexander invaded Persia.


EDIT 2:



On second thought, I've been thinking about Ross' paradox the wrong way. First, define the following deontic operators:




  • it is obligatory that (OB)

  • it is impermissible that (IM)

  • it is omissible that (OM)

  • it is permissible that (PE)

  • it is optional that (OP)


All of these operators can be expressed in terms of OB alone:




  • IM p ↔ OB ~ p

  • OM p ↔ ~ OB p

  • PE p ↔ ~ OB ~ p

  • OP p ↔ (~ OB p) ∧ (~ OB ~ p)


Consider the simple example:




  1. Mail the letter.

  2. Therefore, mail the letter or burn it.


More formally,




  1. OB (mail the letter)

  2. OB (mail the letter ∨ burn the letter)


I don't see anything wrong with 2 anymore, because it's not really presenting a choice! It's not saying that burning the letter is permissible! Just because an obligation entails a second obligation that would be satisfied by an action, it doesn't mean that the first obligation would be satisfied by that action. If you burn the letter, you would have fulfilled a different obligation entailed by the original obligation, but not the original obligation itself. In fact, doing so would make it impossible to fulfill the original obligation of mailing the letter. Thus burning the letter is impermissible, even though mailing the letter or burning it is permissible (and in fact obligatory)!




  1. burn the letter → ~(mail the letter)

  2. mail the letter → ~(burn the letter) [from 1 by contraposition]

  3. OB(mail the letter) → OB(~(burn the letter)) [from 2 by axiom OB-RM]

  4. OB(mail the letter)

  5. OB(~(burn the letter)) [from 3 and 4 by modus ponens]

  6. IM(burn the letter) [from 5 and the definition of IM]


The key point here is that OB (p ∨ q) is perfectly consistent with IM q, because it's not actually expressing a real choice. But how do you express a real choice then, like "pay up or leave" in the context of a restaurant? The proper way to express a real choice between p and q is not



OB (p ∨ q)



but



OB (p ∨ q) ∧ OP p ∧ OP q



In particular, you must specify that p and q are each optional, lest it turns out that one of them was actually obligatory (or impermissible) individually.










share|improve this question

























  • It doesn't mean burn your house down is valid, it means clean your room or burn your house down is valid since at least one of these is true.

    – EternalPropagation
    Dec 6 '18 at 4:22






  • 1





    @EternalPropagation So what's the paradox?

    – user76284
    Dec 6 '18 at 4:26






  • 1





    Paradoxes don't exist.

    – EternalPropagation
    Dec 6 '18 at 4:26






  • 2





    @EternalPropagation Not helpful. I'm asking why it's called a paradox.

    – user76284
    Dec 6 '18 at 4:33













  • "Clean your room" does not seem like a truth bearer; that is, a sentence that could be true or false and nothing else.

    – user4894
    Dec 6 '18 at 7:01














7












7








7


1






Consider the following disjunction introduction:




  1. Your room is clean.

  2. Therefore, your room is clean or your house is burnt down.


Ross' paradox allegedly arises when applying this inference to imperative logic:




  1. Clean your room.

  2. Therefore, clean your room or burn your house down.


Intuitively, 2 doesn't appear to follow from 1. However, it seems to me that this is just due to a syntactic ambiguity in the conclusion. That is, the conclusion could be interpreted in one of two ways:




  1. You should (clean your room or burn your house down).

  2. (You should clean your room) or (you should burn your house down).


The conclusion that follows from "clean your room" is really 2, not 1. Thus I don't see where the paradox arises. More generally, consider a do operator, so that do(x) denotes "x is obligatory" or "I command you to do x". Then the inference





  1. do(x)

  2. Therefore, do(x) or do(y)


is valid but the inference





  1. do(x)

  2. Therefore, do(x or y)


is not. Am I missing something about this purported paradox?



EDIT: Is the underlying problem here the implicit assumption that





  1. do(x)

  2. x → y

  3. Therefore, do(y)


is a valid inference? If so, that doesn't seem right. To see why it's not true in general, consider replacing the do operator with the negation operator:




  1. not(x)

  2. x → y

  3. Therefore, not(y)


This would be a basic formal fallacy called denying the antecedent. It's not true for the modal necessity operator either:




  1. Necessarily, 1 + 1 = 2.

  2. 1 + 1 = 2 → Alexander invaded Persia.

  3. Therefore, necessarily, Alexander invaded Persia.


EDIT 2:



On second thought, I've been thinking about Ross' paradox the wrong way. First, define the following deontic operators:




  • it is obligatory that (OB)

  • it is impermissible that (IM)

  • it is omissible that (OM)

  • it is permissible that (PE)

  • it is optional that (OP)


All of these operators can be expressed in terms of OB alone:




  • IM p ↔ OB ~ p

  • OM p ↔ ~ OB p

  • PE p ↔ ~ OB ~ p

  • OP p ↔ (~ OB p) ∧ (~ OB ~ p)


Consider the simple example:




  1. Mail the letter.

  2. Therefore, mail the letter or burn it.


More formally,




  1. OB (mail the letter)

  2. OB (mail the letter ∨ burn the letter)


I don't see anything wrong with 2 anymore, because it's not really presenting a choice! It's not saying that burning the letter is permissible! Just because an obligation entails a second obligation that would be satisfied by an action, it doesn't mean that the first obligation would be satisfied by that action. If you burn the letter, you would have fulfilled a different obligation entailed by the original obligation, but not the original obligation itself. In fact, doing so would make it impossible to fulfill the original obligation of mailing the letter. Thus burning the letter is impermissible, even though mailing the letter or burning it is permissible (and in fact obligatory)!




  1. burn the letter → ~(mail the letter)

  2. mail the letter → ~(burn the letter) [from 1 by contraposition]

  3. OB(mail the letter) → OB(~(burn the letter)) [from 2 by axiom OB-RM]

  4. OB(mail the letter)

  5. OB(~(burn the letter)) [from 3 and 4 by modus ponens]

  6. IM(burn the letter) [from 5 and the definition of IM]


The key point here is that OB (p ∨ q) is perfectly consistent with IM q, because it's not actually expressing a real choice. But how do you express a real choice then, like "pay up or leave" in the context of a restaurant? The proper way to express a real choice between p and q is not



OB (p ∨ q)



but



OB (p ∨ q) ∧ OP p ∧ OP q



In particular, you must specify that p and q are each optional, lest it turns out that one of them was actually obligatory (or impermissible) individually.










share|improve this question
















Consider the following disjunction introduction:




  1. Your room is clean.

  2. Therefore, your room is clean or your house is burnt down.


Ross' paradox allegedly arises when applying this inference to imperative logic:




  1. Clean your room.

  2. Therefore, clean your room or burn your house down.


Intuitively, 2 doesn't appear to follow from 1. However, it seems to me that this is just due to a syntactic ambiguity in the conclusion. That is, the conclusion could be interpreted in one of two ways:




  1. You should (clean your room or burn your house down).

  2. (You should clean your room) or (you should burn your house down).


The conclusion that follows from "clean your room" is really 2, not 1. Thus I don't see where the paradox arises. More generally, consider a do operator, so that do(x) denotes "x is obligatory" or "I command you to do x". Then the inference





  1. do(x)

  2. Therefore, do(x) or do(y)


is valid but the inference





  1. do(x)

  2. Therefore, do(x or y)


is not. Am I missing something about this purported paradox?



EDIT: Is the underlying problem here the implicit assumption that





  1. do(x)

  2. x → y

  3. Therefore, do(y)


is a valid inference? If so, that doesn't seem right. To see why it's not true in general, consider replacing the do operator with the negation operator:




  1. not(x)

  2. x → y

  3. Therefore, not(y)


This would be a basic formal fallacy called denying the antecedent. It's not true for the modal necessity operator either:




  1. Necessarily, 1 + 1 = 2.

  2. 1 + 1 = 2 → Alexander invaded Persia.

  3. Therefore, necessarily, Alexander invaded Persia.


EDIT 2:



On second thought, I've been thinking about Ross' paradox the wrong way. First, define the following deontic operators:




  • it is obligatory that (OB)

  • it is impermissible that (IM)

  • it is omissible that (OM)

  • it is permissible that (PE)

  • it is optional that (OP)


All of these operators can be expressed in terms of OB alone:




  • IM p ↔ OB ~ p

  • OM p ↔ ~ OB p

  • PE p ↔ ~ OB ~ p

  • OP p ↔ (~ OB p) ∧ (~ OB ~ p)


Consider the simple example:




  1. Mail the letter.

  2. Therefore, mail the letter or burn it.


More formally,




  1. OB (mail the letter)

  2. OB (mail the letter ∨ burn the letter)


I don't see anything wrong with 2 anymore, because it's not really presenting a choice! It's not saying that burning the letter is permissible! Just because an obligation entails a second obligation that would be satisfied by an action, it doesn't mean that the first obligation would be satisfied by that action. If you burn the letter, you would have fulfilled a different obligation entailed by the original obligation, but not the original obligation itself. In fact, doing so would make it impossible to fulfill the original obligation of mailing the letter. Thus burning the letter is impermissible, even though mailing the letter or burning it is permissible (and in fact obligatory)!




  1. burn the letter → ~(mail the letter)

  2. mail the letter → ~(burn the letter) [from 1 by contraposition]

  3. OB(mail the letter) → OB(~(burn the letter)) [from 2 by axiom OB-RM]

  4. OB(mail the letter)

  5. OB(~(burn the letter)) [from 3 and 4 by modus ponens]

  6. IM(burn the letter) [from 5 and the definition of IM]


The key point here is that OB (p ∨ q) is perfectly consistent with IM q, because it's not actually expressing a real choice. But how do you express a real choice then, like "pay up or leave" in the context of a restaurant? The proper way to express a real choice between p and q is not



OB (p ∨ q)



but



OB (p ∨ q) ∧ OP p ∧ OP q



In particular, you must specify that p and q are each optional, lest it turns out that one of them was actually obligatory (or impermissible) individually.







logic paradox deontology






share|improve this question















share|improve this question













share|improve this question




share|improve this question








edited Dec 8 '18 at 2:56







user76284

















asked Dec 6 '18 at 4:02









user76284user76284

1746




1746













  • It doesn't mean burn your house down is valid, it means clean your room or burn your house down is valid since at least one of these is true.

    – EternalPropagation
    Dec 6 '18 at 4:22






  • 1





    @EternalPropagation So what's the paradox?

    – user76284
    Dec 6 '18 at 4:26






  • 1





    Paradoxes don't exist.

    – EternalPropagation
    Dec 6 '18 at 4:26






  • 2





    @EternalPropagation Not helpful. I'm asking why it's called a paradox.

    – user76284
    Dec 6 '18 at 4:33













  • "Clean your room" does not seem like a truth bearer; that is, a sentence that could be true or false and nothing else.

    – user4894
    Dec 6 '18 at 7:01



















  • It doesn't mean burn your house down is valid, it means clean your room or burn your house down is valid since at least one of these is true.

    – EternalPropagation
    Dec 6 '18 at 4:22






  • 1





    @EternalPropagation So what's the paradox?

    – user76284
    Dec 6 '18 at 4:26






  • 1





    Paradoxes don't exist.

    – EternalPropagation
    Dec 6 '18 at 4:26






  • 2





    @EternalPropagation Not helpful. I'm asking why it's called a paradox.

    – user76284
    Dec 6 '18 at 4:33













  • "Clean your room" does not seem like a truth bearer; that is, a sentence that could be true or false and nothing else.

    – user4894
    Dec 6 '18 at 7:01

















It doesn't mean burn your house down is valid, it means clean your room or burn your house down is valid since at least one of these is true.

– EternalPropagation
Dec 6 '18 at 4:22





It doesn't mean burn your house down is valid, it means clean your room or burn your house down is valid since at least one of these is true.

– EternalPropagation
Dec 6 '18 at 4:22




1




1





@EternalPropagation So what's the paradox?

– user76284
Dec 6 '18 at 4:26





@EternalPropagation So what's the paradox?

– user76284
Dec 6 '18 at 4:26




1




1





Paradoxes don't exist.

– EternalPropagation
Dec 6 '18 at 4:26





Paradoxes don't exist.

– EternalPropagation
Dec 6 '18 at 4:26




2




2





@EternalPropagation Not helpful. I'm asking why it's called a paradox.

– user76284
Dec 6 '18 at 4:33







@EternalPropagation Not helpful. I'm asking why it's called a paradox.

– user76284
Dec 6 '18 at 4:33















"Clean your room" does not seem like a truth bearer; that is, a sentence that could be true or false and nothing else.

– user4894
Dec 6 '18 at 7:01





"Clean your room" does not seem like a truth bearer; that is, a sentence that could be true or false and nothing else.

– user4894
Dec 6 '18 at 7:01










3 Answers
3






active

oldest

votes


















3














The issue arises if we consider imperatives, i.e. statements in the form : "Clean your room".



In this case, the standard truth-functional accounts of connectives, that licenses inference patterns like disjunction introduction, seems at odds with natural language practice.



This conclusion is consistent with the standard assumption of mathematical logic that propositions stand for declarative sentences, excluding imperatives.



If we consider instead a sort of "modal" operator, like your "do(x)" (or "should"), things are different.



Consider as the "modality" should; thus "You should (clean your room)" is : p.



From it we have truth-functionally : (p ∨ q), i.e. your 2. above.



But, according to your analysis, we have not : (p ∨ q), i.e. your 1. above.






share|improve this answer

































    3














    I don't think your suggestion resolves the paradox. If you allow that do(x) entails do(x) or do(y), there remains the problem of explaining why you are not left with the option to do y. In ordinary English if Alice says to Bob, "Pay up or leave", we would understand this to mean that it is Bob's choice as to which he does. There does not seem to be any difference between representing this as Do(pay up OR leave) as opposed to Do(pay up) OR Do(leave). The key feature of the paradox is that an element of choice appears to have crept in where it does not belong. We need to find some way of explaining how the element of choice is specified or implied.



    One option would be to accept that an imperative Do( A OR B ) always entails a choice. We might then attempt to develop a distinct imperative logic to account for the circumstances in which it is correct to infer Do( A OR B ). This logic would differ from classical logic, because it would have to exclude disjunction introduction in order to avoid the paradox.



    An alternative approach might be to appeal to Grice's theory of implicature. We might hold that Do( A OR B ) only carries the conversational implicature of a choice. There is an analogy here with uttering a disjunction when answering a question. Suppose Alice asks Bob, "Where is Charlie?" and Bob knows that Charlie is in the library but responds, "Charlie is either in the library or the kitchen". Bob has not said anything untrue. Charlie's being in the library does indeed entail that he is either in the library or the kitchen. But Bob's answer is misleading. Bob is violating Grice's cooperative principle and being less informative than he could be in the circumstances. Alice is entitled to assume that Bob is obeying the cooperative principle and so it is reasonable for her to believe that Bob does not know whether Charlie is in the library or the kitchen. The answer "A or B" does not entail or mean "A or B and I don't know which", but in the circumstances it is a conversational implicature. One way to recognise the difference is that conversational implicatures are cancellable, but meanings are not. Suppose Bob had replied, "Charlie is in the library or the kitchen. I know which, but I'm choosing not to tell you." Here, Bob has expressly cancelled the implicature. Alice is no longer misled into believing that Bob does not know. Bob is still being less informative than he might, but at least he is being honest about it and not deceiving Alice.



    Now, can we carry this over to imperatives? It depends on whether you think the following is plausible. Suppose Alice commands Bob, "Do A or B!" Ordinarily Bob is entitled to assume that Alice is giving him a choice, and it would be misleading, but not strictly incorrect, if Alice in fact wanted Bob to do A and not B. For the implicature to be cancellable, it would have to make sense for Alice to say something like, "Do A or B! I'm not giving you a choice: you must find out which is the right one to do and then do it." If you are willing to accept this, then we can say the same about your example. "Clean your room!" might be taken to entail "Clean your room or burn the house down!" but not "Clean your room or burn the house down and it is your choice which!"






    share|improve this answer
























    • Thanks for your response. "If you allow that do(x) entails do(x) or do(y), there remains the problem of explaining why you are not left with the option to do y." Because it may be the case that (do(x) ∨ do(y)) ∧ ¬do(y). do(x) ∨ do(y) only means it is the case that you are obligated to do x or it is the case that you are obligated to do y, not that it is the case that you are obligated to (do x or do y).

      – user76284
      Dec 7 '18 at 4:23











    • "There does not seem to be any difference between representing this as Do(pay up OR leave) as opposed to Do(pay up) OR Do(leave)." On the contrary: I think this is a great example to distinguish between them. In your example, "Do(pay up OR leave)" is true while "Do(pay up) OR Do(leave)" is false! This is because the latter means I have commanded you to pay up, or I have commanded you to leave, or both, when in fact I have done no such thing! I have commanded the choice ("Do(pay up OR leave)"), but I haven't commanded either option individually ("Do(pay up)", "Do(leave)").

      – user76284
      Dec 7 '18 at 4:30













    • "The key feature of the paradox is that an element of choice appears to have crept in where it does not belong." That's the thing: I don't think "do(x) or do(y)" implies a choice. Rather, it implies that I commanded one or both of those two things. We just don't know which, in the absence of further information. Do you see what I mean? It's the difference between me giving you a choice, and you not knowing which one is the command I gave (epistemic ignorance).

      – user76284
      Dec 7 '18 at 4:30













    • In short: do(x or y) is giving you a choice between (1) do (x and not y), (2) do (y and not x), and (3) do (x and y). do(x) or do(y) means that either do(x) is true, or do(y) is true, or both. If do(x) is true, option 2 is eliminated. If do(y) is true, option 1 is eliminated. If do(x) and do(y) are both true, options 1 and 2 are eliminated. In any case, do(x) or do(y) means that some choices must have been eliminated!

      – user76284
      Dec 7 '18 at 4:41








    • 1





      OK, in which case you are taking the first option and saying that do(A or B) carries the meaning that a choice is involved, while do(A) or do(B) does not. I can only say that I don't detect any such difference in ordinary English usage, but of course there is nothing amiss with urging that this would be a useful revision of usage in order to avoid ambiguity. The conversational implicature option is a way of appealing to the pragmatics rather than the semantics to understand what is intended by the speaker.

      – Bumble
      Dec 7 '18 at 10:31



















    1














    Paul McNamara addresses Ross's paradox in deontic logic where there is an obligation operator, OB. His exposition may help explain why Ross's paradox appears paradoxical to some people even without that operator.



    Consider the example provided by the OP:





    1. Clean your room.

    2. Therefore, clean your room or burn your house down.




    McNamara used a similar example about mailing or burning a letter. As he put it




    ...it seems rather odd to say that an obligation to mail the letter entails an obligation that can be fulfilled by burning the letter (something presumably forbidden), and one that would appear to be violated by not burning it if I don't mail the letter.




    Applying this to the example about cleaning one's room, it seems odd to say that the command to clean one's room can be fulfilled by burning down the house. And if one actually did burn the house down that would violate the command to clean the room.



    The paradox follows from the OB-RM derived rule of standard deontic logic:




    If ⊢ p → q, then ⊢ OBp → OBq




    After substituting p for p and (p ∨ q) for q using OB-RM, one has ⊢ p → (p ∨ q), then ⊢ OBp → OB(p ∨ q). That is, if one is obligated to clean one's room then one is obligated to clean one's room or burn the house down. Furthermore, one could fulfill the obligation to clean one's room by substituting anything one wanted to do rather than burning the house down, such as taking a walk.



    The OP suggests the paradox may be avoided by having a disjunction of two ought statements, OB p ∨ OB q, but that would not be derived from the OB-RM rule which is what is causing the problem. Besides, it would be odd for someone to make both of those commands rather than just the first one to clean one's room.





    Reference



    McNamara, Paul, "Deontic Logic", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2018 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/logic-deontic/.






    share|improve this answer


























    • Thanks. I am deriving OB p ∨ OB q from OB p through disjunction introduction. Since this is taking place outside of the operator, it is perfectly valid. If one ought to do A, then it is the case that either one ought to do A, one ought to do B, or both. The problem, as you point out, is the OB-RM rule, which would force us to accept OB (p ∨ q) as well.

      – user76284
      Dec 7 '18 at 3:29











    • I see from your SEP link that OB-RM is derived from the axioms OB-NEC and OB-K. OB-K seems fine to me under the semantics of obligations/imperatives/commands. However, OB-NEC (if ⊢ p then ⊢ OB p) doesn't seem fine to me at all. For example, it doesn't seem to me that, if you are spitting in my face, you are obligated/I am commanding you to spit in my face.

      – user76284
      Dec 7 '18 at 3:33













    • @user76284 Using OB-RM I can see how one can derive OB(p v q). The proof is in the SEP article I cited. However, I don't know how one can derive OB p v OB q from OB p. The disjunction introduction rule works on propositions such as p or q.

      – Frank Hubeny
      Dec 7 '18 at 3:35






    • 1





      I believe I made a mistake in interpreting OB (p ∨ q) as a choice, and have edited the question accordingly.

      – user76284
      Dec 8 '18 at 3:04






    • 1





      I also misunderstood OB-RM and OB-NEC. See philosophy.stackexchange.com/questions/57738/….

      – user76284
      Dec 8 '18 at 3:32











    Your Answer








    StackExchange.ready(function() {
    var channelOptions = {
    tags: "".split(" "),
    id: "265"
    };
    initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

    StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
    // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
    if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
    StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
    createEditor();
    });
    }
    else {
    createEditor();
    }
    });

    function createEditor() {
    StackExchange.prepareEditor({
    heartbeatType: 'answer',
    autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
    convertImagesToLinks: false,
    noModals: true,
    showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
    reputationToPostImages: null,
    bindNavPrevention: true,
    postfix: "",
    imageUploader: {
    brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
    contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
    allowUrls: true
    },
    noCode: true, onDemand: true,
    discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
    ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
    });


    }
    });














    draft saved

    draft discarded


















    StackExchange.ready(
    function () {
    StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fphilosophy.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f57692%2fis-ross-paradox-really-a-paradox%23new-answer', 'question_page');
    }
    );

    Post as a guest















    Required, but never shown

























    3 Answers
    3






    active

    oldest

    votes








    3 Answers
    3






    active

    oldest

    votes









    active

    oldest

    votes






    active

    oldest

    votes









    3














    The issue arises if we consider imperatives, i.e. statements in the form : "Clean your room".



    In this case, the standard truth-functional accounts of connectives, that licenses inference patterns like disjunction introduction, seems at odds with natural language practice.



    This conclusion is consistent with the standard assumption of mathematical logic that propositions stand for declarative sentences, excluding imperatives.



    If we consider instead a sort of "modal" operator, like your "do(x)" (or "should"), things are different.



    Consider as the "modality" should; thus "You should (clean your room)" is : p.



    From it we have truth-functionally : (p ∨ q), i.e. your 2. above.



    But, according to your analysis, we have not : (p ∨ q), i.e. your 1. above.






    share|improve this answer






























      3














      The issue arises if we consider imperatives, i.e. statements in the form : "Clean your room".



      In this case, the standard truth-functional accounts of connectives, that licenses inference patterns like disjunction introduction, seems at odds with natural language practice.



      This conclusion is consistent with the standard assumption of mathematical logic that propositions stand for declarative sentences, excluding imperatives.



      If we consider instead a sort of "modal" operator, like your "do(x)" (or "should"), things are different.



      Consider as the "modality" should; thus "You should (clean your room)" is : p.



      From it we have truth-functionally : (p ∨ q), i.e. your 2. above.



      But, according to your analysis, we have not : (p ∨ q), i.e. your 1. above.






      share|improve this answer




























        3












        3








        3







        The issue arises if we consider imperatives, i.e. statements in the form : "Clean your room".



        In this case, the standard truth-functional accounts of connectives, that licenses inference patterns like disjunction introduction, seems at odds with natural language practice.



        This conclusion is consistent with the standard assumption of mathematical logic that propositions stand for declarative sentences, excluding imperatives.



        If we consider instead a sort of "modal" operator, like your "do(x)" (or "should"), things are different.



        Consider as the "modality" should; thus "You should (clean your room)" is : p.



        From it we have truth-functionally : (p ∨ q), i.e. your 2. above.



        But, according to your analysis, we have not : (p ∨ q), i.e. your 1. above.






        share|improve this answer















        The issue arises if we consider imperatives, i.e. statements in the form : "Clean your room".



        In this case, the standard truth-functional accounts of connectives, that licenses inference patterns like disjunction introduction, seems at odds with natural language practice.



        This conclusion is consistent with the standard assumption of mathematical logic that propositions stand for declarative sentences, excluding imperatives.



        If we consider instead a sort of "modal" operator, like your "do(x)" (or "should"), things are different.



        Consider as the "modality" should; thus "You should (clean your room)" is : p.



        From it we have truth-functionally : (p ∨ q), i.e. your 2. above.



        But, according to your analysis, we have not : (p ∨ q), i.e. your 1. above.







        share|improve this answer














        share|improve this answer



        share|improve this answer








        edited Dec 6 '18 at 10:00

























        answered Dec 6 '18 at 7:37









        Mauro ALLEGRANZAMauro ALLEGRANZA

        28k21963




        28k21963























            3














            I don't think your suggestion resolves the paradox. If you allow that do(x) entails do(x) or do(y), there remains the problem of explaining why you are not left with the option to do y. In ordinary English if Alice says to Bob, "Pay up or leave", we would understand this to mean that it is Bob's choice as to which he does. There does not seem to be any difference between representing this as Do(pay up OR leave) as opposed to Do(pay up) OR Do(leave). The key feature of the paradox is that an element of choice appears to have crept in where it does not belong. We need to find some way of explaining how the element of choice is specified or implied.



            One option would be to accept that an imperative Do( A OR B ) always entails a choice. We might then attempt to develop a distinct imperative logic to account for the circumstances in which it is correct to infer Do( A OR B ). This logic would differ from classical logic, because it would have to exclude disjunction introduction in order to avoid the paradox.



            An alternative approach might be to appeal to Grice's theory of implicature. We might hold that Do( A OR B ) only carries the conversational implicature of a choice. There is an analogy here with uttering a disjunction when answering a question. Suppose Alice asks Bob, "Where is Charlie?" and Bob knows that Charlie is in the library but responds, "Charlie is either in the library or the kitchen". Bob has not said anything untrue. Charlie's being in the library does indeed entail that he is either in the library or the kitchen. But Bob's answer is misleading. Bob is violating Grice's cooperative principle and being less informative than he could be in the circumstances. Alice is entitled to assume that Bob is obeying the cooperative principle and so it is reasonable for her to believe that Bob does not know whether Charlie is in the library or the kitchen. The answer "A or B" does not entail or mean "A or B and I don't know which", but in the circumstances it is a conversational implicature. One way to recognise the difference is that conversational implicatures are cancellable, but meanings are not. Suppose Bob had replied, "Charlie is in the library or the kitchen. I know which, but I'm choosing not to tell you." Here, Bob has expressly cancelled the implicature. Alice is no longer misled into believing that Bob does not know. Bob is still being less informative than he might, but at least he is being honest about it and not deceiving Alice.



            Now, can we carry this over to imperatives? It depends on whether you think the following is plausible. Suppose Alice commands Bob, "Do A or B!" Ordinarily Bob is entitled to assume that Alice is giving him a choice, and it would be misleading, but not strictly incorrect, if Alice in fact wanted Bob to do A and not B. For the implicature to be cancellable, it would have to make sense for Alice to say something like, "Do A or B! I'm not giving you a choice: you must find out which is the right one to do and then do it." If you are willing to accept this, then we can say the same about your example. "Clean your room!" might be taken to entail "Clean your room or burn the house down!" but not "Clean your room or burn the house down and it is your choice which!"






            share|improve this answer
























            • Thanks for your response. "If you allow that do(x) entails do(x) or do(y), there remains the problem of explaining why you are not left with the option to do y." Because it may be the case that (do(x) ∨ do(y)) ∧ ¬do(y). do(x) ∨ do(y) only means it is the case that you are obligated to do x or it is the case that you are obligated to do y, not that it is the case that you are obligated to (do x or do y).

              – user76284
              Dec 7 '18 at 4:23











            • "There does not seem to be any difference between representing this as Do(pay up OR leave) as opposed to Do(pay up) OR Do(leave)." On the contrary: I think this is a great example to distinguish between them. In your example, "Do(pay up OR leave)" is true while "Do(pay up) OR Do(leave)" is false! This is because the latter means I have commanded you to pay up, or I have commanded you to leave, or both, when in fact I have done no such thing! I have commanded the choice ("Do(pay up OR leave)"), but I haven't commanded either option individually ("Do(pay up)", "Do(leave)").

              – user76284
              Dec 7 '18 at 4:30













            • "The key feature of the paradox is that an element of choice appears to have crept in where it does not belong." That's the thing: I don't think "do(x) or do(y)" implies a choice. Rather, it implies that I commanded one or both of those two things. We just don't know which, in the absence of further information. Do you see what I mean? It's the difference between me giving you a choice, and you not knowing which one is the command I gave (epistemic ignorance).

              – user76284
              Dec 7 '18 at 4:30













            • In short: do(x or y) is giving you a choice between (1) do (x and not y), (2) do (y and not x), and (3) do (x and y). do(x) or do(y) means that either do(x) is true, or do(y) is true, or both. If do(x) is true, option 2 is eliminated. If do(y) is true, option 1 is eliminated. If do(x) and do(y) are both true, options 1 and 2 are eliminated. In any case, do(x) or do(y) means that some choices must have been eliminated!

              – user76284
              Dec 7 '18 at 4:41








            • 1





              OK, in which case you are taking the first option and saying that do(A or B) carries the meaning that a choice is involved, while do(A) or do(B) does not. I can only say that I don't detect any such difference in ordinary English usage, but of course there is nothing amiss with urging that this would be a useful revision of usage in order to avoid ambiguity. The conversational implicature option is a way of appealing to the pragmatics rather than the semantics to understand what is intended by the speaker.

              – Bumble
              Dec 7 '18 at 10:31
















            3














            I don't think your suggestion resolves the paradox. If you allow that do(x) entails do(x) or do(y), there remains the problem of explaining why you are not left with the option to do y. In ordinary English if Alice says to Bob, "Pay up or leave", we would understand this to mean that it is Bob's choice as to which he does. There does not seem to be any difference between representing this as Do(pay up OR leave) as opposed to Do(pay up) OR Do(leave). The key feature of the paradox is that an element of choice appears to have crept in where it does not belong. We need to find some way of explaining how the element of choice is specified or implied.



            One option would be to accept that an imperative Do( A OR B ) always entails a choice. We might then attempt to develop a distinct imperative logic to account for the circumstances in which it is correct to infer Do( A OR B ). This logic would differ from classical logic, because it would have to exclude disjunction introduction in order to avoid the paradox.



            An alternative approach might be to appeal to Grice's theory of implicature. We might hold that Do( A OR B ) only carries the conversational implicature of a choice. There is an analogy here with uttering a disjunction when answering a question. Suppose Alice asks Bob, "Where is Charlie?" and Bob knows that Charlie is in the library but responds, "Charlie is either in the library or the kitchen". Bob has not said anything untrue. Charlie's being in the library does indeed entail that he is either in the library or the kitchen. But Bob's answer is misleading. Bob is violating Grice's cooperative principle and being less informative than he could be in the circumstances. Alice is entitled to assume that Bob is obeying the cooperative principle and so it is reasonable for her to believe that Bob does not know whether Charlie is in the library or the kitchen. The answer "A or B" does not entail or mean "A or B and I don't know which", but in the circumstances it is a conversational implicature. One way to recognise the difference is that conversational implicatures are cancellable, but meanings are not. Suppose Bob had replied, "Charlie is in the library or the kitchen. I know which, but I'm choosing not to tell you." Here, Bob has expressly cancelled the implicature. Alice is no longer misled into believing that Bob does not know. Bob is still being less informative than he might, but at least he is being honest about it and not deceiving Alice.



            Now, can we carry this over to imperatives? It depends on whether you think the following is plausible. Suppose Alice commands Bob, "Do A or B!" Ordinarily Bob is entitled to assume that Alice is giving him a choice, and it would be misleading, but not strictly incorrect, if Alice in fact wanted Bob to do A and not B. For the implicature to be cancellable, it would have to make sense for Alice to say something like, "Do A or B! I'm not giving you a choice: you must find out which is the right one to do and then do it." If you are willing to accept this, then we can say the same about your example. "Clean your room!" might be taken to entail "Clean your room or burn the house down!" but not "Clean your room or burn the house down and it is your choice which!"






            share|improve this answer
























            • Thanks for your response. "If you allow that do(x) entails do(x) or do(y), there remains the problem of explaining why you are not left with the option to do y." Because it may be the case that (do(x) ∨ do(y)) ∧ ¬do(y). do(x) ∨ do(y) only means it is the case that you are obligated to do x or it is the case that you are obligated to do y, not that it is the case that you are obligated to (do x or do y).

              – user76284
              Dec 7 '18 at 4:23











            • "There does not seem to be any difference between representing this as Do(pay up OR leave) as opposed to Do(pay up) OR Do(leave)." On the contrary: I think this is a great example to distinguish between them. In your example, "Do(pay up OR leave)" is true while "Do(pay up) OR Do(leave)" is false! This is because the latter means I have commanded you to pay up, or I have commanded you to leave, or both, when in fact I have done no such thing! I have commanded the choice ("Do(pay up OR leave)"), but I haven't commanded either option individually ("Do(pay up)", "Do(leave)").

              – user76284
              Dec 7 '18 at 4:30













            • "The key feature of the paradox is that an element of choice appears to have crept in where it does not belong." That's the thing: I don't think "do(x) or do(y)" implies a choice. Rather, it implies that I commanded one or both of those two things. We just don't know which, in the absence of further information. Do you see what I mean? It's the difference between me giving you a choice, and you not knowing which one is the command I gave (epistemic ignorance).

              – user76284
              Dec 7 '18 at 4:30













            • In short: do(x or y) is giving you a choice between (1) do (x and not y), (2) do (y and not x), and (3) do (x and y). do(x) or do(y) means that either do(x) is true, or do(y) is true, or both. If do(x) is true, option 2 is eliminated. If do(y) is true, option 1 is eliminated. If do(x) and do(y) are both true, options 1 and 2 are eliminated. In any case, do(x) or do(y) means that some choices must have been eliminated!

              – user76284
              Dec 7 '18 at 4:41








            • 1





              OK, in which case you are taking the first option and saying that do(A or B) carries the meaning that a choice is involved, while do(A) or do(B) does not. I can only say that I don't detect any such difference in ordinary English usage, but of course there is nothing amiss with urging that this would be a useful revision of usage in order to avoid ambiguity. The conversational implicature option is a way of appealing to the pragmatics rather than the semantics to understand what is intended by the speaker.

              – Bumble
              Dec 7 '18 at 10:31














            3












            3








            3







            I don't think your suggestion resolves the paradox. If you allow that do(x) entails do(x) or do(y), there remains the problem of explaining why you are not left with the option to do y. In ordinary English if Alice says to Bob, "Pay up or leave", we would understand this to mean that it is Bob's choice as to which he does. There does not seem to be any difference between representing this as Do(pay up OR leave) as opposed to Do(pay up) OR Do(leave). The key feature of the paradox is that an element of choice appears to have crept in where it does not belong. We need to find some way of explaining how the element of choice is specified or implied.



            One option would be to accept that an imperative Do( A OR B ) always entails a choice. We might then attempt to develop a distinct imperative logic to account for the circumstances in which it is correct to infer Do( A OR B ). This logic would differ from classical logic, because it would have to exclude disjunction introduction in order to avoid the paradox.



            An alternative approach might be to appeal to Grice's theory of implicature. We might hold that Do( A OR B ) only carries the conversational implicature of a choice. There is an analogy here with uttering a disjunction when answering a question. Suppose Alice asks Bob, "Where is Charlie?" and Bob knows that Charlie is in the library but responds, "Charlie is either in the library or the kitchen". Bob has not said anything untrue. Charlie's being in the library does indeed entail that he is either in the library or the kitchen. But Bob's answer is misleading. Bob is violating Grice's cooperative principle and being less informative than he could be in the circumstances. Alice is entitled to assume that Bob is obeying the cooperative principle and so it is reasonable for her to believe that Bob does not know whether Charlie is in the library or the kitchen. The answer "A or B" does not entail or mean "A or B and I don't know which", but in the circumstances it is a conversational implicature. One way to recognise the difference is that conversational implicatures are cancellable, but meanings are not. Suppose Bob had replied, "Charlie is in the library or the kitchen. I know which, but I'm choosing not to tell you." Here, Bob has expressly cancelled the implicature. Alice is no longer misled into believing that Bob does not know. Bob is still being less informative than he might, but at least he is being honest about it and not deceiving Alice.



            Now, can we carry this over to imperatives? It depends on whether you think the following is plausible. Suppose Alice commands Bob, "Do A or B!" Ordinarily Bob is entitled to assume that Alice is giving him a choice, and it would be misleading, but not strictly incorrect, if Alice in fact wanted Bob to do A and not B. For the implicature to be cancellable, it would have to make sense for Alice to say something like, "Do A or B! I'm not giving you a choice: you must find out which is the right one to do and then do it." If you are willing to accept this, then we can say the same about your example. "Clean your room!" might be taken to entail "Clean your room or burn the house down!" but not "Clean your room or burn the house down and it is your choice which!"






            share|improve this answer













            I don't think your suggestion resolves the paradox. If you allow that do(x) entails do(x) or do(y), there remains the problem of explaining why you are not left with the option to do y. In ordinary English if Alice says to Bob, "Pay up or leave", we would understand this to mean that it is Bob's choice as to which he does. There does not seem to be any difference between representing this as Do(pay up OR leave) as opposed to Do(pay up) OR Do(leave). The key feature of the paradox is that an element of choice appears to have crept in where it does not belong. We need to find some way of explaining how the element of choice is specified or implied.



            One option would be to accept that an imperative Do( A OR B ) always entails a choice. We might then attempt to develop a distinct imperative logic to account for the circumstances in which it is correct to infer Do( A OR B ). This logic would differ from classical logic, because it would have to exclude disjunction introduction in order to avoid the paradox.



            An alternative approach might be to appeal to Grice's theory of implicature. We might hold that Do( A OR B ) only carries the conversational implicature of a choice. There is an analogy here with uttering a disjunction when answering a question. Suppose Alice asks Bob, "Where is Charlie?" and Bob knows that Charlie is in the library but responds, "Charlie is either in the library or the kitchen". Bob has not said anything untrue. Charlie's being in the library does indeed entail that he is either in the library or the kitchen. But Bob's answer is misleading. Bob is violating Grice's cooperative principle and being less informative than he could be in the circumstances. Alice is entitled to assume that Bob is obeying the cooperative principle and so it is reasonable for her to believe that Bob does not know whether Charlie is in the library or the kitchen. The answer "A or B" does not entail or mean "A or B and I don't know which", but in the circumstances it is a conversational implicature. One way to recognise the difference is that conversational implicatures are cancellable, but meanings are not. Suppose Bob had replied, "Charlie is in the library or the kitchen. I know which, but I'm choosing not to tell you." Here, Bob has expressly cancelled the implicature. Alice is no longer misled into believing that Bob does not know. Bob is still being less informative than he might, but at least he is being honest about it and not deceiving Alice.



            Now, can we carry this over to imperatives? It depends on whether you think the following is plausible. Suppose Alice commands Bob, "Do A or B!" Ordinarily Bob is entitled to assume that Alice is giving him a choice, and it would be misleading, but not strictly incorrect, if Alice in fact wanted Bob to do A and not B. For the implicature to be cancellable, it would have to make sense for Alice to say something like, "Do A or B! I'm not giving you a choice: you must find out which is the right one to do and then do it." If you are willing to accept this, then we can say the same about your example. "Clean your room!" might be taken to entail "Clean your room or burn the house down!" but not "Clean your room or burn the house down and it is your choice which!"







            share|improve this answer












            share|improve this answer



            share|improve this answer










            answered Dec 6 '18 at 10:17









            BumbleBumble

            7,56921132




            7,56921132













            • Thanks for your response. "If you allow that do(x) entails do(x) or do(y), there remains the problem of explaining why you are not left with the option to do y." Because it may be the case that (do(x) ∨ do(y)) ∧ ¬do(y). do(x) ∨ do(y) only means it is the case that you are obligated to do x or it is the case that you are obligated to do y, not that it is the case that you are obligated to (do x or do y).

              – user76284
              Dec 7 '18 at 4:23











            • "There does not seem to be any difference between representing this as Do(pay up OR leave) as opposed to Do(pay up) OR Do(leave)." On the contrary: I think this is a great example to distinguish between them. In your example, "Do(pay up OR leave)" is true while "Do(pay up) OR Do(leave)" is false! This is because the latter means I have commanded you to pay up, or I have commanded you to leave, or both, when in fact I have done no such thing! I have commanded the choice ("Do(pay up OR leave)"), but I haven't commanded either option individually ("Do(pay up)", "Do(leave)").

              – user76284
              Dec 7 '18 at 4:30













            • "The key feature of the paradox is that an element of choice appears to have crept in where it does not belong." That's the thing: I don't think "do(x) or do(y)" implies a choice. Rather, it implies that I commanded one or both of those two things. We just don't know which, in the absence of further information. Do you see what I mean? It's the difference between me giving you a choice, and you not knowing which one is the command I gave (epistemic ignorance).

              – user76284
              Dec 7 '18 at 4:30













            • In short: do(x or y) is giving you a choice between (1) do (x and not y), (2) do (y and not x), and (3) do (x and y). do(x) or do(y) means that either do(x) is true, or do(y) is true, or both. If do(x) is true, option 2 is eliminated. If do(y) is true, option 1 is eliminated. If do(x) and do(y) are both true, options 1 and 2 are eliminated. In any case, do(x) or do(y) means that some choices must have been eliminated!

              – user76284
              Dec 7 '18 at 4:41








            • 1





              OK, in which case you are taking the first option and saying that do(A or B) carries the meaning that a choice is involved, while do(A) or do(B) does not. I can only say that I don't detect any such difference in ordinary English usage, but of course there is nothing amiss with urging that this would be a useful revision of usage in order to avoid ambiguity. The conversational implicature option is a way of appealing to the pragmatics rather than the semantics to understand what is intended by the speaker.

              – Bumble
              Dec 7 '18 at 10:31



















            • Thanks for your response. "If you allow that do(x) entails do(x) or do(y), there remains the problem of explaining why you are not left with the option to do y." Because it may be the case that (do(x) ∨ do(y)) ∧ ¬do(y). do(x) ∨ do(y) only means it is the case that you are obligated to do x or it is the case that you are obligated to do y, not that it is the case that you are obligated to (do x or do y).

              – user76284
              Dec 7 '18 at 4:23











            • "There does not seem to be any difference between representing this as Do(pay up OR leave) as opposed to Do(pay up) OR Do(leave)." On the contrary: I think this is a great example to distinguish between them. In your example, "Do(pay up OR leave)" is true while "Do(pay up) OR Do(leave)" is false! This is because the latter means I have commanded you to pay up, or I have commanded you to leave, or both, when in fact I have done no such thing! I have commanded the choice ("Do(pay up OR leave)"), but I haven't commanded either option individually ("Do(pay up)", "Do(leave)").

              – user76284
              Dec 7 '18 at 4:30













            • "The key feature of the paradox is that an element of choice appears to have crept in where it does not belong." That's the thing: I don't think "do(x) or do(y)" implies a choice. Rather, it implies that I commanded one or both of those two things. We just don't know which, in the absence of further information. Do you see what I mean? It's the difference between me giving you a choice, and you not knowing which one is the command I gave (epistemic ignorance).

              – user76284
              Dec 7 '18 at 4:30













            • In short: do(x or y) is giving you a choice between (1) do (x and not y), (2) do (y and not x), and (3) do (x and y). do(x) or do(y) means that either do(x) is true, or do(y) is true, or both. If do(x) is true, option 2 is eliminated. If do(y) is true, option 1 is eliminated. If do(x) and do(y) are both true, options 1 and 2 are eliminated. In any case, do(x) or do(y) means that some choices must have been eliminated!

              – user76284
              Dec 7 '18 at 4:41








            • 1





              OK, in which case you are taking the first option and saying that do(A or B) carries the meaning that a choice is involved, while do(A) or do(B) does not. I can only say that I don't detect any such difference in ordinary English usage, but of course there is nothing amiss with urging that this would be a useful revision of usage in order to avoid ambiguity. The conversational implicature option is a way of appealing to the pragmatics rather than the semantics to understand what is intended by the speaker.

              – Bumble
              Dec 7 '18 at 10:31

















            Thanks for your response. "If you allow that do(x) entails do(x) or do(y), there remains the problem of explaining why you are not left with the option to do y." Because it may be the case that (do(x) ∨ do(y)) ∧ ¬do(y). do(x) ∨ do(y) only means it is the case that you are obligated to do x or it is the case that you are obligated to do y, not that it is the case that you are obligated to (do x or do y).

            – user76284
            Dec 7 '18 at 4:23





            Thanks for your response. "If you allow that do(x) entails do(x) or do(y), there remains the problem of explaining why you are not left with the option to do y." Because it may be the case that (do(x) ∨ do(y)) ∧ ¬do(y). do(x) ∨ do(y) only means it is the case that you are obligated to do x or it is the case that you are obligated to do y, not that it is the case that you are obligated to (do x or do y).

            – user76284
            Dec 7 '18 at 4:23













            "There does not seem to be any difference between representing this as Do(pay up OR leave) as opposed to Do(pay up) OR Do(leave)." On the contrary: I think this is a great example to distinguish between them. In your example, "Do(pay up OR leave)" is true while "Do(pay up) OR Do(leave)" is false! This is because the latter means I have commanded you to pay up, or I have commanded you to leave, or both, when in fact I have done no such thing! I have commanded the choice ("Do(pay up OR leave)"), but I haven't commanded either option individually ("Do(pay up)", "Do(leave)").

            – user76284
            Dec 7 '18 at 4:30







            "There does not seem to be any difference between representing this as Do(pay up OR leave) as opposed to Do(pay up) OR Do(leave)." On the contrary: I think this is a great example to distinguish between them. In your example, "Do(pay up OR leave)" is true while "Do(pay up) OR Do(leave)" is false! This is because the latter means I have commanded you to pay up, or I have commanded you to leave, or both, when in fact I have done no such thing! I have commanded the choice ("Do(pay up OR leave)"), but I haven't commanded either option individually ("Do(pay up)", "Do(leave)").

            – user76284
            Dec 7 '18 at 4:30















            "The key feature of the paradox is that an element of choice appears to have crept in where it does not belong." That's the thing: I don't think "do(x) or do(y)" implies a choice. Rather, it implies that I commanded one or both of those two things. We just don't know which, in the absence of further information. Do you see what I mean? It's the difference between me giving you a choice, and you not knowing which one is the command I gave (epistemic ignorance).

            – user76284
            Dec 7 '18 at 4:30







            "The key feature of the paradox is that an element of choice appears to have crept in where it does not belong." That's the thing: I don't think "do(x) or do(y)" implies a choice. Rather, it implies that I commanded one or both of those two things. We just don't know which, in the absence of further information. Do you see what I mean? It's the difference between me giving you a choice, and you not knowing which one is the command I gave (epistemic ignorance).

            – user76284
            Dec 7 '18 at 4:30















            In short: do(x or y) is giving you a choice between (1) do (x and not y), (2) do (y and not x), and (3) do (x and y). do(x) or do(y) means that either do(x) is true, or do(y) is true, or both. If do(x) is true, option 2 is eliminated. If do(y) is true, option 1 is eliminated. If do(x) and do(y) are both true, options 1 and 2 are eliminated. In any case, do(x) or do(y) means that some choices must have been eliminated!

            – user76284
            Dec 7 '18 at 4:41







            In short: do(x or y) is giving you a choice between (1) do (x and not y), (2) do (y and not x), and (3) do (x and y). do(x) or do(y) means that either do(x) is true, or do(y) is true, or both. If do(x) is true, option 2 is eliminated. If do(y) is true, option 1 is eliminated. If do(x) and do(y) are both true, options 1 and 2 are eliminated. In any case, do(x) or do(y) means that some choices must have been eliminated!

            – user76284
            Dec 7 '18 at 4:41






            1




            1





            OK, in which case you are taking the first option and saying that do(A or B) carries the meaning that a choice is involved, while do(A) or do(B) does not. I can only say that I don't detect any such difference in ordinary English usage, but of course there is nothing amiss with urging that this would be a useful revision of usage in order to avoid ambiguity. The conversational implicature option is a way of appealing to the pragmatics rather than the semantics to understand what is intended by the speaker.

            – Bumble
            Dec 7 '18 at 10:31





            OK, in which case you are taking the first option and saying that do(A or B) carries the meaning that a choice is involved, while do(A) or do(B) does not. I can only say that I don't detect any such difference in ordinary English usage, but of course there is nothing amiss with urging that this would be a useful revision of usage in order to avoid ambiguity. The conversational implicature option is a way of appealing to the pragmatics rather than the semantics to understand what is intended by the speaker.

            – Bumble
            Dec 7 '18 at 10:31











            1














            Paul McNamara addresses Ross's paradox in deontic logic where there is an obligation operator, OB. His exposition may help explain why Ross's paradox appears paradoxical to some people even without that operator.



            Consider the example provided by the OP:





            1. Clean your room.

            2. Therefore, clean your room or burn your house down.




            McNamara used a similar example about mailing or burning a letter. As he put it




            ...it seems rather odd to say that an obligation to mail the letter entails an obligation that can be fulfilled by burning the letter (something presumably forbidden), and one that would appear to be violated by not burning it if I don't mail the letter.




            Applying this to the example about cleaning one's room, it seems odd to say that the command to clean one's room can be fulfilled by burning down the house. And if one actually did burn the house down that would violate the command to clean the room.



            The paradox follows from the OB-RM derived rule of standard deontic logic:




            If ⊢ p → q, then ⊢ OBp → OBq




            After substituting p for p and (p ∨ q) for q using OB-RM, one has ⊢ p → (p ∨ q), then ⊢ OBp → OB(p ∨ q). That is, if one is obligated to clean one's room then one is obligated to clean one's room or burn the house down. Furthermore, one could fulfill the obligation to clean one's room by substituting anything one wanted to do rather than burning the house down, such as taking a walk.



            The OP suggests the paradox may be avoided by having a disjunction of two ought statements, OB p ∨ OB q, but that would not be derived from the OB-RM rule which is what is causing the problem. Besides, it would be odd for someone to make both of those commands rather than just the first one to clean one's room.





            Reference



            McNamara, Paul, "Deontic Logic", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2018 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/logic-deontic/.






            share|improve this answer


























            • Thanks. I am deriving OB p ∨ OB q from OB p through disjunction introduction. Since this is taking place outside of the operator, it is perfectly valid. If one ought to do A, then it is the case that either one ought to do A, one ought to do B, or both. The problem, as you point out, is the OB-RM rule, which would force us to accept OB (p ∨ q) as well.

              – user76284
              Dec 7 '18 at 3:29











            • I see from your SEP link that OB-RM is derived from the axioms OB-NEC and OB-K. OB-K seems fine to me under the semantics of obligations/imperatives/commands. However, OB-NEC (if ⊢ p then ⊢ OB p) doesn't seem fine to me at all. For example, it doesn't seem to me that, if you are spitting in my face, you are obligated/I am commanding you to spit in my face.

              – user76284
              Dec 7 '18 at 3:33













            • @user76284 Using OB-RM I can see how one can derive OB(p v q). The proof is in the SEP article I cited. However, I don't know how one can derive OB p v OB q from OB p. The disjunction introduction rule works on propositions such as p or q.

              – Frank Hubeny
              Dec 7 '18 at 3:35






            • 1





              I believe I made a mistake in interpreting OB (p ∨ q) as a choice, and have edited the question accordingly.

              – user76284
              Dec 8 '18 at 3:04






            • 1





              I also misunderstood OB-RM and OB-NEC. See philosophy.stackexchange.com/questions/57738/….

              – user76284
              Dec 8 '18 at 3:32
















            1














            Paul McNamara addresses Ross's paradox in deontic logic where there is an obligation operator, OB. His exposition may help explain why Ross's paradox appears paradoxical to some people even without that operator.



            Consider the example provided by the OP:





            1. Clean your room.

            2. Therefore, clean your room or burn your house down.




            McNamara used a similar example about mailing or burning a letter. As he put it




            ...it seems rather odd to say that an obligation to mail the letter entails an obligation that can be fulfilled by burning the letter (something presumably forbidden), and one that would appear to be violated by not burning it if I don't mail the letter.




            Applying this to the example about cleaning one's room, it seems odd to say that the command to clean one's room can be fulfilled by burning down the house. And if one actually did burn the house down that would violate the command to clean the room.



            The paradox follows from the OB-RM derived rule of standard deontic logic:




            If ⊢ p → q, then ⊢ OBp → OBq




            After substituting p for p and (p ∨ q) for q using OB-RM, one has ⊢ p → (p ∨ q), then ⊢ OBp → OB(p ∨ q). That is, if one is obligated to clean one's room then one is obligated to clean one's room or burn the house down. Furthermore, one could fulfill the obligation to clean one's room by substituting anything one wanted to do rather than burning the house down, such as taking a walk.



            The OP suggests the paradox may be avoided by having a disjunction of two ought statements, OB p ∨ OB q, but that would not be derived from the OB-RM rule which is what is causing the problem. Besides, it would be odd for someone to make both of those commands rather than just the first one to clean one's room.





            Reference



            McNamara, Paul, "Deontic Logic", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2018 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/logic-deontic/.






            share|improve this answer


























            • Thanks. I am deriving OB p ∨ OB q from OB p through disjunction introduction. Since this is taking place outside of the operator, it is perfectly valid. If one ought to do A, then it is the case that either one ought to do A, one ought to do B, or both. The problem, as you point out, is the OB-RM rule, which would force us to accept OB (p ∨ q) as well.

              – user76284
              Dec 7 '18 at 3:29











            • I see from your SEP link that OB-RM is derived from the axioms OB-NEC and OB-K. OB-K seems fine to me under the semantics of obligations/imperatives/commands. However, OB-NEC (if ⊢ p then ⊢ OB p) doesn't seem fine to me at all. For example, it doesn't seem to me that, if you are spitting in my face, you are obligated/I am commanding you to spit in my face.

              – user76284
              Dec 7 '18 at 3:33













            • @user76284 Using OB-RM I can see how one can derive OB(p v q). The proof is in the SEP article I cited. However, I don't know how one can derive OB p v OB q from OB p. The disjunction introduction rule works on propositions such as p or q.

              – Frank Hubeny
              Dec 7 '18 at 3:35






            • 1





              I believe I made a mistake in interpreting OB (p ∨ q) as a choice, and have edited the question accordingly.

              – user76284
              Dec 8 '18 at 3:04






            • 1





              I also misunderstood OB-RM and OB-NEC. See philosophy.stackexchange.com/questions/57738/….

              – user76284
              Dec 8 '18 at 3:32














            1












            1








            1







            Paul McNamara addresses Ross's paradox in deontic logic where there is an obligation operator, OB. His exposition may help explain why Ross's paradox appears paradoxical to some people even without that operator.



            Consider the example provided by the OP:





            1. Clean your room.

            2. Therefore, clean your room or burn your house down.




            McNamara used a similar example about mailing or burning a letter. As he put it




            ...it seems rather odd to say that an obligation to mail the letter entails an obligation that can be fulfilled by burning the letter (something presumably forbidden), and one that would appear to be violated by not burning it if I don't mail the letter.




            Applying this to the example about cleaning one's room, it seems odd to say that the command to clean one's room can be fulfilled by burning down the house. And if one actually did burn the house down that would violate the command to clean the room.



            The paradox follows from the OB-RM derived rule of standard deontic logic:




            If ⊢ p → q, then ⊢ OBp → OBq




            After substituting p for p and (p ∨ q) for q using OB-RM, one has ⊢ p → (p ∨ q), then ⊢ OBp → OB(p ∨ q). That is, if one is obligated to clean one's room then one is obligated to clean one's room or burn the house down. Furthermore, one could fulfill the obligation to clean one's room by substituting anything one wanted to do rather than burning the house down, such as taking a walk.



            The OP suggests the paradox may be avoided by having a disjunction of two ought statements, OB p ∨ OB q, but that would not be derived from the OB-RM rule which is what is causing the problem. Besides, it would be odd for someone to make both of those commands rather than just the first one to clean one's room.





            Reference



            McNamara, Paul, "Deontic Logic", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2018 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/logic-deontic/.






            share|improve this answer















            Paul McNamara addresses Ross's paradox in deontic logic where there is an obligation operator, OB. His exposition may help explain why Ross's paradox appears paradoxical to some people even without that operator.



            Consider the example provided by the OP:





            1. Clean your room.

            2. Therefore, clean your room or burn your house down.




            McNamara used a similar example about mailing or burning a letter. As he put it




            ...it seems rather odd to say that an obligation to mail the letter entails an obligation that can be fulfilled by burning the letter (something presumably forbidden), and one that would appear to be violated by not burning it if I don't mail the letter.




            Applying this to the example about cleaning one's room, it seems odd to say that the command to clean one's room can be fulfilled by burning down the house. And if one actually did burn the house down that would violate the command to clean the room.



            The paradox follows from the OB-RM derived rule of standard deontic logic:




            If ⊢ p → q, then ⊢ OBp → OBq




            After substituting p for p and (p ∨ q) for q using OB-RM, one has ⊢ p → (p ∨ q), then ⊢ OBp → OB(p ∨ q). That is, if one is obligated to clean one's room then one is obligated to clean one's room or burn the house down. Furthermore, one could fulfill the obligation to clean one's room by substituting anything one wanted to do rather than burning the house down, such as taking a walk.



            The OP suggests the paradox may be avoided by having a disjunction of two ought statements, OB p ∨ OB q, but that would not be derived from the OB-RM rule which is what is causing the problem. Besides, it would be odd for someone to make both of those commands rather than just the first one to clean one's room.





            Reference



            McNamara, Paul, "Deontic Logic", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2018 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/logic-deontic/.







            share|improve this answer














            share|improve this answer



            share|improve this answer








            edited Dec 8 '18 at 11:48

























            answered Dec 6 '18 at 18:22









            Frank HubenyFrank Hubeny

            7,11251444




            7,11251444













            • Thanks. I am deriving OB p ∨ OB q from OB p through disjunction introduction. Since this is taking place outside of the operator, it is perfectly valid. If one ought to do A, then it is the case that either one ought to do A, one ought to do B, or both. The problem, as you point out, is the OB-RM rule, which would force us to accept OB (p ∨ q) as well.

              – user76284
              Dec 7 '18 at 3:29











            • I see from your SEP link that OB-RM is derived from the axioms OB-NEC and OB-K. OB-K seems fine to me under the semantics of obligations/imperatives/commands. However, OB-NEC (if ⊢ p then ⊢ OB p) doesn't seem fine to me at all. For example, it doesn't seem to me that, if you are spitting in my face, you are obligated/I am commanding you to spit in my face.

              – user76284
              Dec 7 '18 at 3:33













            • @user76284 Using OB-RM I can see how one can derive OB(p v q). The proof is in the SEP article I cited. However, I don't know how one can derive OB p v OB q from OB p. The disjunction introduction rule works on propositions such as p or q.

              – Frank Hubeny
              Dec 7 '18 at 3:35






            • 1





              I believe I made a mistake in interpreting OB (p ∨ q) as a choice, and have edited the question accordingly.

              – user76284
              Dec 8 '18 at 3:04






            • 1





              I also misunderstood OB-RM and OB-NEC. See philosophy.stackexchange.com/questions/57738/….

              – user76284
              Dec 8 '18 at 3:32



















            • Thanks. I am deriving OB p ∨ OB q from OB p through disjunction introduction. Since this is taking place outside of the operator, it is perfectly valid. If one ought to do A, then it is the case that either one ought to do A, one ought to do B, or both. The problem, as you point out, is the OB-RM rule, which would force us to accept OB (p ∨ q) as well.

              – user76284
              Dec 7 '18 at 3:29











            • I see from your SEP link that OB-RM is derived from the axioms OB-NEC and OB-K. OB-K seems fine to me under the semantics of obligations/imperatives/commands. However, OB-NEC (if ⊢ p then ⊢ OB p) doesn't seem fine to me at all. For example, it doesn't seem to me that, if you are spitting in my face, you are obligated/I am commanding you to spit in my face.

              – user76284
              Dec 7 '18 at 3:33













            • @user76284 Using OB-RM I can see how one can derive OB(p v q). The proof is in the SEP article I cited. However, I don't know how one can derive OB p v OB q from OB p. The disjunction introduction rule works on propositions such as p or q.

              – Frank Hubeny
              Dec 7 '18 at 3:35






            • 1





              I believe I made a mistake in interpreting OB (p ∨ q) as a choice, and have edited the question accordingly.

              – user76284
              Dec 8 '18 at 3:04






            • 1





              I also misunderstood OB-RM and OB-NEC. See philosophy.stackexchange.com/questions/57738/….

              – user76284
              Dec 8 '18 at 3:32

















            Thanks. I am deriving OB p ∨ OB q from OB p through disjunction introduction. Since this is taking place outside of the operator, it is perfectly valid. If one ought to do A, then it is the case that either one ought to do A, one ought to do B, or both. The problem, as you point out, is the OB-RM rule, which would force us to accept OB (p ∨ q) as well.

            – user76284
            Dec 7 '18 at 3:29





            Thanks. I am deriving OB p ∨ OB q from OB p through disjunction introduction. Since this is taking place outside of the operator, it is perfectly valid. If one ought to do A, then it is the case that either one ought to do A, one ought to do B, or both. The problem, as you point out, is the OB-RM rule, which would force us to accept OB (p ∨ q) as well.

            – user76284
            Dec 7 '18 at 3:29













            I see from your SEP link that OB-RM is derived from the axioms OB-NEC and OB-K. OB-K seems fine to me under the semantics of obligations/imperatives/commands. However, OB-NEC (if ⊢ p then ⊢ OB p) doesn't seem fine to me at all. For example, it doesn't seem to me that, if you are spitting in my face, you are obligated/I am commanding you to spit in my face.

            – user76284
            Dec 7 '18 at 3:33







            I see from your SEP link that OB-RM is derived from the axioms OB-NEC and OB-K. OB-K seems fine to me under the semantics of obligations/imperatives/commands. However, OB-NEC (if ⊢ p then ⊢ OB p) doesn't seem fine to me at all. For example, it doesn't seem to me that, if you are spitting in my face, you are obligated/I am commanding you to spit in my face.

            – user76284
            Dec 7 '18 at 3:33















            @user76284 Using OB-RM I can see how one can derive OB(p v q). The proof is in the SEP article I cited. However, I don't know how one can derive OB p v OB q from OB p. The disjunction introduction rule works on propositions such as p or q.

            – Frank Hubeny
            Dec 7 '18 at 3:35





            @user76284 Using OB-RM I can see how one can derive OB(p v q). The proof is in the SEP article I cited. However, I don't know how one can derive OB p v OB q from OB p. The disjunction introduction rule works on propositions such as p or q.

            – Frank Hubeny
            Dec 7 '18 at 3:35




            1




            1





            I believe I made a mistake in interpreting OB (p ∨ q) as a choice, and have edited the question accordingly.

            – user76284
            Dec 8 '18 at 3:04





            I believe I made a mistake in interpreting OB (p ∨ q) as a choice, and have edited the question accordingly.

            – user76284
            Dec 8 '18 at 3:04




            1




            1





            I also misunderstood OB-RM and OB-NEC. See philosophy.stackexchange.com/questions/57738/….

            – user76284
            Dec 8 '18 at 3:32





            I also misunderstood OB-RM and OB-NEC. See philosophy.stackexchange.com/questions/57738/….

            – user76284
            Dec 8 '18 at 3:32


















            draft saved

            draft discarded




















































            Thanks for contributing an answer to Philosophy Stack Exchange!


            • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

            But avoid



            • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

            • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


            To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




            draft saved


            draft discarded














            StackExchange.ready(
            function () {
            StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fphilosophy.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f57692%2fis-ross-paradox-really-a-paradox%23new-answer', 'question_page');
            }
            );

            Post as a guest















            Required, but never shown





















































            Required, but never shown














            Required, but never shown












            Required, but never shown







            Required, but never shown

































            Required, but never shown














            Required, but never shown












            Required, but never shown







            Required, but never shown







            Popular posts from this blog

            Berounka

            Fiat S.p.A.

            Type 'String' is not a subtype of type 'int' of 'index'