Doubts about Cantor's diagonal argument












-1












$begingroup$


I was studying about countability or non-contability of sets when I saw the Cantor's diagonal argument to prove that the set of real numbers are not-countable. My question is that in the proof it is always possible to find a new real number that was not in the listed before, but it is kinda obvious, since the set of real number is infinity, we can always find a new real different from the previous one, like with integers for example. If we try to find a bijection f between integers and naturals, given that we know the value of $f$ in ${1,2,ldots,n}$ the value of $f(n+1)$ will be different than any number in ${f(1),f(2),ldots,f(n)}$, since $f$ is bijective then $f$ is injective.










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$

















    -1












    $begingroup$


    I was studying about countability or non-contability of sets when I saw the Cantor's diagonal argument to prove that the set of real numbers are not-countable. My question is that in the proof it is always possible to find a new real number that was not in the listed before, but it is kinda obvious, since the set of real number is infinity, we can always find a new real different from the previous one, like with integers for example. If we try to find a bijection f between integers and naturals, given that we know the value of $f$ in ${1,2,ldots,n}$ the value of $f(n+1)$ will be different than any number in ${f(1),f(2),ldots,f(n)}$, since $f$ is bijective then $f$ is injective.










    share|cite|improve this question











    $endgroup$















      -1












      -1








      -1





      $begingroup$


      I was studying about countability or non-contability of sets when I saw the Cantor's diagonal argument to prove that the set of real numbers are not-countable. My question is that in the proof it is always possible to find a new real number that was not in the listed before, but it is kinda obvious, since the set of real number is infinity, we can always find a new real different from the previous one, like with integers for example. If we try to find a bijection f between integers and naturals, given that we know the value of $f$ in ${1,2,ldots,n}$ the value of $f(n+1)$ will be different than any number in ${f(1),f(2),ldots,f(n)}$, since $f$ is bijective then $f$ is injective.










      share|cite|improve this question











      $endgroup$




      I was studying about countability or non-contability of sets when I saw the Cantor's diagonal argument to prove that the set of real numbers are not-countable. My question is that in the proof it is always possible to find a new real number that was not in the listed before, but it is kinda obvious, since the set of real number is infinity, we can always find a new real different from the previous one, like with integers for example. If we try to find a bijection f between integers and naturals, given that we know the value of $f$ in ${1,2,ldots,n}$ the value of $f(n+1)$ will be different than any number in ${f(1),f(2),ldots,f(n)}$, since $f$ is bijective then $f$ is injective.







      elementary-set-theory proof-explanation






      share|cite|improve this question















      share|cite|improve this question













      share|cite|improve this question




      share|cite|improve this question








      edited Dec 9 '18 at 18:11







      eipi10

















      asked Dec 9 '18 at 17:43









      eipi10eipi10

      33




      33






















          3 Answers
          3






          active

          oldest

          votes


















          0












          $begingroup$

          We say that two sets are equinumerous if there exists a bijection between them. That is, sets $A$ and $B$ admit a function $$f colon A rightarrow B$$ such that every element of $B$ is mapped to by exactly one element of $A$ (we say $f$ is both injective and surjective). So, if you give you an element $a in A$, I can give you a unique element of $b in B$ that is "associated" with $a$ via $f$; that is exactly the case when $f(a) = b$. This correspondence goes both ways: Given $b$, I can find $a$ by applying the inverse of $f$ (the existence of inverses is essential to bijections).





          An infinite set $A$ is countable if it is equinumerous with the natural numbers which are denoted by $mathbb{N}$. We can show that $A$ is countable by exhibiting a bijection between $A$ and $mathbb{N}$. The integers are countable for example, via the bijection $$ f colon mathbb{N} rightarrow mathbb{Z} \ f(0) = 0, ; f(1) = -1, ; f(2) = 1, ; f(3) = -2, ; f(4) = 2, ; f(5) = -3, ldots$$ Similarly, the rationals $mathbb{Q}$ are countable.



          A defining characteristic of countable sets is that we can list their elements. This is by virtue of being in a bijection with the natural numbers; via the bijective function, we can associate any natural number with a unique element, just as we can in a list. Consider, for example, the bijection between $mathbb{N}$ and $mathbb{Z}$ as a list (LHS is element of the naturals, RHS an element of the integers in a bijective correspondence):



          $$begin{array}{c|c}
          mathbb{N} & mathbb{Z} \ hline
          0 & 0 \
          1 & -1 \
          2 & 1 \
          3 & -2 \
          4 & 2 \
          5 & -3
          end{array}$$



          and so on.





          Cantor's argument says that there is no way of listing all reals in such a list indexed by the natural numbers. While we know that the reals are infinite (the naturals are infinite, and each natural number is also a real number), this proves that there are more reals than there are naturals.



          You are right in the sense that whenever we consider ${ f(0), ldots, f(n-1) }$, where $f$ is a bijection from infinite $A$ to infinite $B$, then $f(n)$ will be different from each $f(i)$ for $i < n$. But that's not enough. For a bijection $f$ from $mathbb{N}$ to $mathbb{R}$, we would need for any real number $r$ a unique $m$ in $mathbb{N}$ such that $f(m) = r$. In your analogy, fix any real number $r$. Then considering any natural number $m$, if $r notin { f(0), ldots, f(m) }$, there must exist some integer $n > m$ such that $r in { f(0), ldots, f(n) }$. Cantor's diagonal argument shows that given any infinite list ${ f(0), f(1), ldots }$, there is always a real $r'$ that is not in that list.






          share|cite|improve this answer









          $endgroup$





















            1












            $begingroup$

            Cantor's diagonal proof has nothing to do with finding real numbers which had not been “listed before”. We start with a list of real numbers and then we find a new real number which is nowhere on that list.






            share|cite|improve this answer









            $endgroup$













            • $begingroup$
              So what you do is make something like a construction of f(1), f(2), and it goes on. But, when you make a bijection from N to Z when can always find a new integer, so why is this argument correct?
              $endgroup$
              – eipi10
              Dec 9 '18 at 17:49












            • $begingroup$
              Yes. We ahve an infinite list ${f(n),|,ninmathbb{N}}$ and we prove that there is a real number $r$ different from every $f(n)$.
              $endgroup$
              – José Carlos Santos
              Dec 9 '18 at 17:51










            • $begingroup$
              @eipi10 No, when you find a bijection between naturals and integers you then cannot "find a new integer"...whatever that means. Try it and if you find something like that tell us.
              $endgroup$
              – DonAntonio
              Dec 9 '18 at 17:54












            • $begingroup$
              What has the existence of a bijection between $mathbb N$ and $mathbb Z$ to do with Cantor's proof?
              $endgroup$
              – José Carlos Santos
              Dec 9 '18 at 17:54










            • $begingroup$
              But, there's a problem, when this argument is done, it is considered that the natural numers is finite, since it is considered a finite list
              $endgroup$
              – eipi10
              Dec 9 '18 at 17:54



















            0












            $begingroup$

            Cantor's diagonal proof gets misrepresented in many ways. These misrepresentations cause much confusion about it. One of them seems to be what you are asking about. (Another is that used the set of real numbers. In fact, it intentionally did not use that set. It can, with an additional step, so I will continue as if it did.)



            What the significant part of the proof shows, directly and not "by contradiction," is what you called "obvious":




            • If you have a function whose domain is the natural numbers and whose co-domain is the real numbers between 0 and 1,

            • Then that function is not a surjection.


            The only thing that can be called a proof by contradiction, is what Cantor deduced from it: A bijection cannot exist. If you assume one does, it both is (by definition), and is not (by the proof), a surjection.






            share|cite|improve this answer









            $endgroup$













              Your Answer





              StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
              return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
              StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
              StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
              });
              });
              }, "mathjax-editing");

              StackExchange.ready(function() {
              var channelOptions = {
              tags: "".split(" "),
              id: "69"
              };
              initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

              StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
              // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
              if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
              StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
              createEditor();
              });
              }
              else {
              createEditor();
              }
              });

              function createEditor() {
              StackExchange.prepareEditor({
              heartbeatType: 'answer',
              autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
              convertImagesToLinks: true,
              noModals: true,
              showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
              reputationToPostImages: 10,
              bindNavPrevention: true,
              postfix: "",
              imageUploader: {
              brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
              contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
              allowUrls: true
              },
              noCode: true, onDemand: true,
              discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
              ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
              });


              }
              });














              draft saved

              draft discarded


















              StackExchange.ready(
              function () {
              StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3032670%2fdoubts-about-cantors-diagonal-argument%23new-answer', 'question_page');
              }
              );

              Post as a guest















              Required, but never shown

























              3 Answers
              3






              active

              oldest

              votes








              3 Answers
              3






              active

              oldest

              votes









              active

              oldest

              votes






              active

              oldest

              votes









              0












              $begingroup$

              We say that two sets are equinumerous if there exists a bijection between them. That is, sets $A$ and $B$ admit a function $$f colon A rightarrow B$$ such that every element of $B$ is mapped to by exactly one element of $A$ (we say $f$ is both injective and surjective). So, if you give you an element $a in A$, I can give you a unique element of $b in B$ that is "associated" with $a$ via $f$; that is exactly the case when $f(a) = b$. This correspondence goes both ways: Given $b$, I can find $a$ by applying the inverse of $f$ (the existence of inverses is essential to bijections).





              An infinite set $A$ is countable if it is equinumerous with the natural numbers which are denoted by $mathbb{N}$. We can show that $A$ is countable by exhibiting a bijection between $A$ and $mathbb{N}$. The integers are countable for example, via the bijection $$ f colon mathbb{N} rightarrow mathbb{Z} \ f(0) = 0, ; f(1) = -1, ; f(2) = 1, ; f(3) = -2, ; f(4) = 2, ; f(5) = -3, ldots$$ Similarly, the rationals $mathbb{Q}$ are countable.



              A defining characteristic of countable sets is that we can list their elements. This is by virtue of being in a bijection with the natural numbers; via the bijective function, we can associate any natural number with a unique element, just as we can in a list. Consider, for example, the bijection between $mathbb{N}$ and $mathbb{Z}$ as a list (LHS is element of the naturals, RHS an element of the integers in a bijective correspondence):



              $$begin{array}{c|c}
              mathbb{N} & mathbb{Z} \ hline
              0 & 0 \
              1 & -1 \
              2 & 1 \
              3 & -2 \
              4 & 2 \
              5 & -3
              end{array}$$



              and so on.





              Cantor's argument says that there is no way of listing all reals in such a list indexed by the natural numbers. While we know that the reals are infinite (the naturals are infinite, and each natural number is also a real number), this proves that there are more reals than there are naturals.



              You are right in the sense that whenever we consider ${ f(0), ldots, f(n-1) }$, where $f$ is a bijection from infinite $A$ to infinite $B$, then $f(n)$ will be different from each $f(i)$ for $i < n$. But that's not enough. For a bijection $f$ from $mathbb{N}$ to $mathbb{R}$, we would need for any real number $r$ a unique $m$ in $mathbb{N}$ such that $f(m) = r$. In your analogy, fix any real number $r$. Then considering any natural number $m$, if $r notin { f(0), ldots, f(m) }$, there must exist some integer $n > m$ such that $r in { f(0), ldots, f(n) }$. Cantor's diagonal argument shows that given any infinite list ${ f(0), f(1), ldots }$, there is always a real $r'$ that is not in that list.






              share|cite|improve this answer









              $endgroup$


















                0












                $begingroup$

                We say that two sets are equinumerous if there exists a bijection between them. That is, sets $A$ and $B$ admit a function $$f colon A rightarrow B$$ such that every element of $B$ is mapped to by exactly one element of $A$ (we say $f$ is both injective and surjective). So, if you give you an element $a in A$, I can give you a unique element of $b in B$ that is "associated" with $a$ via $f$; that is exactly the case when $f(a) = b$. This correspondence goes both ways: Given $b$, I can find $a$ by applying the inverse of $f$ (the existence of inverses is essential to bijections).





                An infinite set $A$ is countable if it is equinumerous with the natural numbers which are denoted by $mathbb{N}$. We can show that $A$ is countable by exhibiting a bijection between $A$ and $mathbb{N}$. The integers are countable for example, via the bijection $$ f colon mathbb{N} rightarrow mathbb{Z} \ f(0) = 0, ; f(1) = -1, ; f(2) = 1, ; f(3) = -2, ; f(4) = 2, ; f(5) = -3, ldots$$ Similarly, the rationals $mathbb{Q}$ are countable.



                A defining characteristic of countable sets is that we can list their elements. This is by virtue of being in a bijection with the natural numbers; via the bijective function, we can associate any natural number with a unique element, just as we can in a list. Consider, for example, the bijection between $mathbb{N}$ and $mathbb{Z}$ as a list (LHS is element of the naturals, RHS an element of the integers in a bijective correspondence):



                $$begin{array}{c|c}
                mathbb{N} & mathbb{Z} \ hline
                0 & 0 \
                1 & -1 \
                2 & 1 \
                3 & -2 \
                4 & 2 \
                5 & -3
                end{array}$$



                and so on.





                Cantor's argument says that there is no way of listing all reals in such a list indexed by the natural numbers. While we know that the reals are infinite (the naturals are infinite, and each natural number is also a real number), this proves that there are more reals than there are naturals.



                You are right in the sense that whenever we consider ${ f(0), ldots, f(n-1) }$, where $f$ is a bijection from infinite $A$ to infinite $B$, then $f(n)$ will be different from each $f(i)$ for $i < n$. But that's not enough. For a bijection $f$ from $mathbb{N}$ to $mathbb{R}$, we would need for any real number $r$ a unique $m$ in $mathbb{N}$ such that $f(m) = r$. In your analogy, fix any real number $r$. Then considering any natural number $m$, if $r notin { f(0), ldots, f(m) }$, there must exist some integer $n > m$ such that $r in { f(0), ldots, f(n) }$. Cantor's diagonal argument shows that given any infinite list ${ f(0), f(1), ldots }$, there is always a real $r'$ that is not in that list.






                share|cite|improve this answer









                $endgroup$
















                  0












                  0








                  0





                  $begingroup$

                  We say that two sets are equinumerous if there exists a bijection between them. That is, sets $A$ and $B$ admit a function $$f colon A rightarrow B$$ such that every element of $B$ is mapped to by exactly one element of $A$ (we say $f$ is both injective and surjective). So, if you give you an element $a in A$, I can give you a unique element of $b in B$ that is "associated" with $a$ via $f$; that is exactly the case when $f(a) = b$. This correspondence goes both ways: Given $b$, I can find $a$ by applying the inverse of $f$ (the existence of inverses is essential to bijections).





                  An infinite set $A$ is countable if it is equinumerous with the natural numbers which are denoted by $mathbb{N}$. We can show that $A$ is countable by exhibiting a bijection between $A$ and $mathbb{N}$. The integers are countable for example, via the bijection $$ f colon mathbb{N} rightarrow mathbb{Z} \ f(0) = 0, ; f(1) = -1, ; f(2) = 1, ; f(3) = -2, ; f(4) = 2, ; f(5) = -3, ldots$$ Similarly, the rationals $mathbb{Q}$ are countable.



                  A defining characteristic of countable sets is that we can list their elements. This is by virtue of being in a bijection with the natural numbers; via the bijective function, we can associate any natural number with a unique element, just as we can in a list. Consider, for example, the bijection between $mathbb{N}$ and $mathbb{Z}$ as a list (LHS is element of the naturals, RHS an element of the integers in a bijective correspondence):



                  $$begin{array}{c|c}
                  mathbb{N} & mathbb{Z} \ hline
                  0 & 0 \
                  1 & -1 \
                  2 & 1 \
                  3 & -2 \
                  4 & 2 \
                  5 & -3
                  end{array}$$



                  and so on.





                  Cantor's argument says that there is no way of listing all reals in such a list indexed by the natural numbers. While we know that the reals are infinite (the naturals are infinite, and each natural number is also a real number), this proves that there are more reals than there are naturals.



                  You are right in the sense that whenever we consider ${ f(0), ldots, f(n-1) }$, where $f$ is a bijection from infinite $A$ to infinite $B$, then $f(n)$ will be different from each $f(i)$ for $i < n$. But that's not enough. For a bijection $f$ from $mathbb{N}$ to $mathbb{R}$, we would need for any real number $r$ a unique $m$ in $mathbb{N}$ such that $f(m) = r$. In your analogy, fix any real number $r$. Then considering any natural number $m$, if $r notin { f(0), ldots, f(m) }$, there must exist some integer $n > m$ such that $r in { f(0), ldots, f(n) }$. Cantor's diagonal argument shows that given any infinite list ${ f(0), f(1), ldots }$, there is always a real $r'$ that is not in that list.






                  share|cite|improve this answer









                  $endgroup$



                  We say that two sets are equinumerous if there exists a bijection between them. That is, sets $A$ and $B$ admit a function $$f colon A rightarrow B$$ such that every element of $B$ is mapped to by exactly one element of $A$ (we say $f$ is both injective and surjective). So, if you give you an element $a in A$, I can give you a unique element of $b in B$ that is "associated" with $a$ via $f$; that is exactly the case when $f(a) = b$. This correspondence goes both ways: Given $b$, I can find $a$ by applying the inverse of $f$ (the existence of inverses is essential to bijections).





                  An infinite set $A$ is countable if it is equinumerous with the natural numbers which are denoted by $mathbb{N}$. We can show that $A$ is countable by exhibiting a bijection between $A$ and $mathbb{N}$. The integers are countable for example, via the bijection $$ f colon mathbb{N} rightarrow mathbb{Z} \ f(0) = 0, ; f(1) = -1, ; f(2) = 1, ; f(3) = -2, ; f(4) = 2, ; f(5) = -3, ldots$$ Similarly, the rationals $mathbb{Q}$ are countable.



                  A defining characteristic of countable sets is that we can list their elements. This is by virtue of being in a bijection with the natural numbers; via the bijective function, we can associate any natural number with a unique element, just as we can in a list. Consider, for example, the bijection between $mathbb{N}$ and $mathbb{Z}$ as a list (LHS is element of the naturals, RHS an element of the integers in a bijective correspondence):



                  $$begin{array}{c|c}
                  mathbb{N} & mathbb{Z} \ hline
                  0 & 0 \
                  1 & -1 \
                  2 & 1 \
                  3 & -2 \
                  4 & 2 \
                  5 & -3
                  end{array}$$



                  and so on.





                  Cantor's argument says that there is no way of listing all reals in such a list indexed by the natural numbers. While we know that the reals are infinite (the naturals are infinite, and each natural number is also a real number), this proves that there are more reals than there are naturals.



                  You are right in the sense that whenever we consider ${ f(0), ldots, f(n-1) }$, where $f$ is a bijection from infinite $A$ to infinite $B$, then $f(n)$ will be different from each $f(i)$ for $i < n$. But that's not enough. For a bijection $f$ from $mathbb{N}$ to $mathbb{R}$, we would need for any real number $r$ a unique $m$ in $mathbb{N}$ such that $f(m) = r$. In your analogy, fix any real number $r$. Then considering any natural number $m$, if $r notin { f(0), ldots, f(m) }$, there must exist some integer $n > m$ such that $r in { f(0), ldots, f(n) }$. Cantor's diagonal argument shows that given any infinite list ${ f(0), f(1), ldots }$, there is always a real $r'$ that is not in that list.







                  share|cite|improve this answer












                  share|cite|improve this answer



                  share|cite|improve this answer










                  answered Dec 9 '18 at 18:50









                  MacRanceMacRance

                  1226




                  1226























                      1












                      $begingroup$

                      Cantor's diagonal proof has nothing to do with finding real numbers which had not been “listed before”. We start with a list of real numbers and then we find a new real number which is nowhere on that list.






                      share|cite|improve this answer









                      $endgroup$













                      • $begingroup$
                        So what you do is make something like a construction of f(1), f(2), and it goes on. But, when you make a bijection from N to Z when can always find a new integer, so why is this argument correct?
                        $endgroup$
                        – eipi10
                        Dec 9 '18 at 17:49












                      • $begingroup$
                        Yes. We ahve an infinite list ${f(n),|,ninmathbb{N}}$ and we prove that there is a real number $r$ different from every $f(n)$.
                        $endgroup$
                        – José Carlos Santos
                        Dec 9 '18 at 17:51










                      • $begingroup$
                        @eipi10 No, when you find a bijection between naturals and integers you then cannot "find a new integer"...whatever that means. Try it and if you find something like that tell us.
                        $endgroup$
                        – DonAntonio
                        Dec 9 '18 at 17:54












                      • $begingroup$
                        What has the existence of a bijection between $mathbb N$ and $mathbb Z$ to do with Cantor's proof?
                        $endgroup$
                        – José Carlos Santos
                        Dec 9 '18 at 17:54










                      • $begingroup$
                        But, there's a problem, when this argument is done, it is considered that the natural numers is finite, since it is considered a finite list
                        $endgroup$
                        – eipi10
                        Dec 9 '18 at 17:54
















                      1












                      $begingroup$

                      Cantor's diagonal proof has nothing to do with finding real numbers which had not been “listed before”. We start with a list of real numbers and then we find a new real number which is nowhere on that list.






                      share|cite|improve this answer









                      $endgroup$













                      • $begingroup$
                        So what you do is make something like a construction of f(1), f(2), and it goes on. But, when you make a bijection from N to Z when can always find a new integer, so why is this argument correct?
                        $endgroup$
                        – eipi10
                        Dec 9 '18 at 17:49












                      • $begingroup$
                        Yes. We ahve an infinite list ${f(n),|,ninmathbb{N}}$ and we prove that there is a real number $r$ different from every $f(n)$.
                        $endgroup$
                        – José Carlos Santos
                        Dec 9 '18 at 17:51










                      • $begingroup$
                        @eipi10 No, when you find a bijection between naturals and integers you then cannot "find a new integer"...whatever that means. Try it and if you find something like that tell us.
                        $endgroup$
                        – DonAntonio
                        Dec 9 '18 at 17:54












                      • $begingroup$
                        What has the existence of a bijection between $mathbb N$ and $mathbb Z$ to do with Cantor's proof?
                        $endgroup$
                        – José Carlos Santos
                        Dec 9 '18 at 17:54










                      • $begingroup$
                        But, there's a problem, when this argument is done, it is considered that the natural numers is finite, since it is considered a finite list
                        $endgroup$
                        – eipi10
                        Dec 9 '18 at 17:54














                      1












                      1








                      1





                      $begingroup$

                      Cantor's diagonal proof has nothing to do with finding real numbers which had not been “listed before”. We start with a list of real numbers and then we find a new real number which is nowhere on that list.






                      share|cite|improve this answer









                      $endgroup$



                      Cantor's diagonal proof has nothing to do with finding real numbers which had not been “listed before”. We start with a list of real numbers and then we find a new real number which is nowhere on that list.







                      share|cite|improve this answer












                      share|cite|improve this answer



                      share|cite|improve this answer










                      answered Dec 9 '18 at 17:47









                      José Carlos SantosJosé Carlos Santos

                      156k22125227




                      156k22125227












                      • $begingroup$
                        So what you do is make something like a construction of f(1), f(2), and it goes on. But, when you make a bijection from N to Z when can always find a new integer, so why is this argument correct?
                        $endgroup$
                        – eipi10
                        Dec 9 '18 at 17:49












                      • $begingroup$
                        Yes. We ahve an infinite list ${f(n),|,ninmathbb{N}}$ and we prove that there is a real number $r$ different from every $f(n)$.
                        $endgroup$
                        – José Carlos Santos
                        Dec 9 '18 at 17:51










                      • $begingroup$
                        @eipi10 No, when you find a bijection between naturals and integers you then cannot "find a new integer"...whatever that means. Try it and if you find something like that tell us.
                        $endgroup$
                        – DonAntonio
                        Dec 9 '18 at 17:54












                      • $begingroup$
                        What has the existence of a bijection between $mathbb N$ and $mathbb Z$ to do with Cantor's proof?
                        $endgroup$
                        – José Carlos Santos
                        Dec 9 '18 at 17:54










                      • $begingroup$
                        But, there's a problem, when this argument is done, it is considered that the natural numers is finite, since it is considered a finite list
                        $endgroup$
                        – eipi10
                        Dec 9 '18 at 17:54


















                      • $begingroup$
                        So what you do is make something like a construction of f(1), f(2), and it goes on. But, when you make a bijection from N to Z when can always find a new integer, so why is this argument correct?
                        $endgroup$
                        – eipi10
                        Dec 9 '18 at 17:49












                      • $begingroup$
                        Yes. We ahve an infinite list ${f(n),|,ninmathbb{N}}$ and we prove that there is a real number $r$ different from every $f(n)$.
                        $endgroup$
                        – José Carlos Santos
                        Dec 9 '18 at 17:51










                      • $begingroup$
                        @eipi10 No, when you find a bijection between naturals and integers you then cannot "find a new integer"...whatever that means. Try it and if you find something like that tell us.
                        $endgroup$
                        – DonAntonio
                        Dec 9 '18 at 17:54












                      • $begingroup$
                        What has the existence of a bijection between $mathbb N$ and $mathbb Z$ to do with Cantor's proof?
                        $endgroup$
                        – José Carlos Santos
                        Dec 9 '18 at 17:54










                      • $begingroup$
                        But, there's a problem, when this argument is done, it is considered that the natural numers is finite, since it is considered a finite list
                        $endgroup$
                        – eipi10
                        Dec 9 '18 at 17:54
















                      $begingroup$
                      So what you do is make something like a construction of f(1), f(2), and it goes on. But, when you make a bijection from N to Z when can always find a new integer, so why is this argument correct?
                      $endgroup$
                      – eipi10
                      Dec 9 '18 at 17:49






                      $begingroup$
                      So what you do is make something like a construction of f(1), f(2), and it goes on. But, when you make a bijection from N to Z when can always find a new integer, so why is this argument correct?
                      $endgroup$
                      – eipi10
                      Dec 9 '18 at 17:49














                      $begingroup$
                      Yes. We ahve an infinite list ${f(n),|,ninmathbb{N}}$ and we prove that there is a real number $r$ different from every $f(n)$.
                      $endgroup$
                      – José Carlos Santos
                      Dec 9 '18 at 17:51




                      $begingroup$
                      Yes. We ahve an infinite list ${f(n),|,ninmathbb{N}}$ and we prove that there is a real number $r$ different from every $f(n)$.
                      $endgroup$
                      – José Carlos Santos
                      Dec 9 '18 at 17:51












                      $begingroup$
                      @eipi10 No, when you find a bijection between naturals and integers you then cannot "find a new integer"...whatever that means. Try it and if you find something like that tell us.
                      $endgroup$
                      – DonAntonio
                      Dec 9 '18 at 17:54






                      $begingroup$
                      @eipi10 No, when you find a bijection between naturals and integers you then cannot "find a new integer"...whatever that means. Try it and if you find something like that tell us.
                      $endgroup$
                      – DonAntonio
                      Dec 9 '18 at 17:54














                      $begingroup$
                      What has the existence of a bijection between $mathbb N$ and $mathbb Z$ to do with Cantor's proof?
                      $endgroup$
                      – José Carlos Santos
                      Dec 9 '18 at 17:54




                      $begingroup$
                      What has the existence of a bijection between $mathbb N$ and $mathbb Z$ to do with Cantor's proof?
                      $endgroup$
                      – José Carlos Santos
                      Dec 9 '18 at 17:54












                      $begingroup$
                      But, there's a problem, when this argument is done, it is considered that the natural numers is finite, since it is considered a finite list
                      $endgroup$
                      – eipi10
                      Dec 9 '18 at 17:54




                      $begingroup$
                      But, there's a problem, when this argument is done, it is considered that the natural numers is finite, since it is considered a finite list
                      $endgroup$
                      – eipi10
                      Dec 9 '18 at 17:54











                      0












                      $begingroup$

                      Cantor's diagonal proof gets misrepresented in many ways. These misrepresentations cause much confusion about it. One of them seems to be what you are asking about. (Another is that used the set of real numbers. In fact, it intentionally did not use that set. It can, with an additional step, so I will continue as if it did.)



                      What the significant part of the proof shows, directly and not "by contradiction," is what you called "obvious":




                      • If you have a function whose domain is the natural numbers and whose co-domain is the real numbers between 0 and 1,

                      • Then that function is not a surjection.


                      The only thing that can be called a proof by contradiction, is what Cantor deduced from it: A bijection cannot exist. If you assume one does, it both is (by definition), and is not (by the proof), a surjection.






                      share|cite|improve this answer









                      $endgroup$


















                        0












                        $begingroup$

                        Cantor's diagonal proof gets misrepresented in many ways. These misrepresentations cause much confusion about it. One of them seems to be what you are asking about. (Another is that used the set of real numbers. In fact, it intentionally did not use that set. It can, with an additional step, so I will continue as if it did.)



                        What the significant part of the proof shows, directly and not "by contradiction," is what you called "obvious":




                        • If you have a function whose domain is the natural numbers and whose co-domain is the real numbers between 0 and 1,

                        • Then that function is not a surjection.


                        The only thing that can be called a proof by contradiction, is what Cantor deduced from it: A bijection cannot exist. If you assume one does, it both is (by definition), and is not (by the proof), a surjection.






                        share|cite|improve this answer









                        $endgroup$
















                          0












                          0








                          0





                          $begingroup$

                          Cantor's diagonal proof gets misrepresented in many ways. These misrepresentations cause much confusion about it. One of them seems to be what you are asking about. (Another is that used the set of real numbers. In fact, it intentionally did not use that set. It can, with an additional step, so I will continue as if it did.)



                          What the significant part of the proof shows, directly and not "by contradiction," is what you called "obvious":




                          • If you have a function whose domain is the natural numbers and whose co-domain is the real numbers between 0 and 1,

                          • Then that function is not a surjection.


                          The only thing that can be called a proof by contradiction, is what Cantor deduced from it: A bijection cannot exist. If you assume one does, it both is (by definition), and is not (by the proof), a surjection.






                          share|cite|improve this answer









                          $endgroup$



                          Cantor's diagonal proof gets misrepresented in many ways. These misrepresentations cause much confusion about it. One of them seems to be what you are asking about. (Another is that used the set of real numbers. In fact, it intentionally did not use that set. It can, with an additional step, so I will continue as if it did.)



                          What the significant part of the proof shows, directly and not "by contradiction," is what you called "obvious":




                          • If you have a function whose domain is the natural numbers and whose co-domain is the real numbers between 0 and 1,

                          • Then that function is not a surjection.


                          The only thing that can be called a proof by contradiction, is what Cantor deduced from it: A bijection cannot exist. If you assume one does, it both is (by definition), and is not (by the proof), a surjection.







                          share|cite|improve this answer












                          share|cite|improve this answer



                          share|cite|improve this answer










                          answered Dec 11 '18 at 21:58









                          JeffJoJeffJo

                          1554




                          1554






























                              draft saved

                              draft discarded




















































                              Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


                              • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

                              But avoid



                              • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

                              • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


                              Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


                              To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




                              draft saved


                              draft discarded














                              StackExchange.ready(
                              function () {
                              StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3032670%2fdoubts-about-cantors-diagonal-argument%23new-answer', 'question_page');
                              }
                              );

                              Post as a guest















                              Required, but never shown





















































                              Required, but never shown














                              Required, but never shown












                              Required, but never shown







                              Required, but never shown

































                              Required, but never shown














                              Required, but never shown












                              Required, but never shown







                              Required, but never shown







                              Popular posts from this blog

                              Berounka

                              Fiat S.p.A.

                              Type 'String' is not a subtype of type 'int' of 'index'