Is it true that $0.999999999dots=1$?
up vote
252
down vote
favorite
I'm told by smart people that
$$0.999999999dots=1$$
and I believe them, but is there a proof that explains why this is?
real-analysis algebra-precalculus decimal-expansion
|
show 9 more comments
up vote
252
down vote
favorite
I'm told by smart people that
$$0.999999999dots=1$$
and I believe them, but is there a proof that explains why this is?
real-analysis algebra-precalculus decimal-expansion
27
Seriously people what's with all the duplicates? Check and see if someone has already given your answer first!
– Noah Snyder
Jul 20 '10 at 20:28
78
Let me say a word about why 1/3 = .33333... is not obvious at all. What does it mean to say that some number is 1/3? Well division is the operation that undoes multiplication, so it means that it's a number that when you multiply by 3 you get 1. Well what happens when you multiply .3333... times 3? You get .9999... So unless you already know that .99999...=1 then you can't prove that 1/3 = .3333... The fact that .9999...=1 is more basic than the fact that 1/3 = .33333....!
– Noah Snyder
Jul 20 '10 at 21:32
11
Between any two different numbers, there is always another number between them. there is no number between 0.999... and 1
– Joao
Apr 28 '14 at 3:07
4
New prospective answerers, please heed Noah Snyder's comment from over five years ago. It's all the more valuable now.
– Brian Tung
Jan 15 '16 at 23:12
2
@BT: yes, it is a real number, and the question is not meaningless nor stupid. The number $0.999cdots $ is a perfectly well-defined real number: $sum_{k=1}^infty frac9 {10^k}$. It just happens to be the real number that we usually call "one".
– Martin Argerami
Dec 15 '16 at 5:55
|
show 9 more comments
up vote
252
down vote
favorite
up vote
252
down vote
favorite
I'm told by smart people that
$$0.999999999dots=1$$
and I believe them, but is there a proof that explains why this is?
real-analysis algebra-precalculus decimal-expansion
I'm told by smart people that
$$0.999999999dots=1$$
and I believe them, but is there a proof that explains why this is?
real-analysis algebra-precalculus decimal-expansion
real-analysis algebra-precalculus decimal-expansion
edited May 30 at 21:40
community wiki
26 revs, 17 users 36%
Michael Hardy
27
Seriously people what's with all the duplicates? Check and see if someone has already given your answer first!
– Noah Snyder
Jul 20 '10 at 20:28
78
Let me say a word about why 1/3 = .33333... is not obvious at all. What does it mean to say that some number is 1/3? Well division is the operation that undoes multiplication, so it means that it's a number that when you multiply by 3 you get 1. Well what happens when you multiply .3333... times 3? You get .9999... So unless you already know that .99999...=1 then you can't prove that 1/3 = .3333... The fact that .9999...=1 is more basic than the fact that 1/3 = .33333....!
– Noah Snyder
Jul 20 '10 at 21:32
11
Between any two different numbers, there is always another number between them. there is no number between 0.999... and 1
– Joao
Apr 28 '14 at 3:07
4
New prospective answerers, please heed Noah Snyder's comment from over five years ago. It's all the more valuable now.
– Brian Tung
Jan 15 '16 at 23:12
2
@BT: yes, it is a real number, and the question is not meaningless nor stupid. The number $0.999cdots $ is a perfectly well-defined real number: $sum_{k=1}^infty frac9 {10^k}$. It just happens to be the real number that we usually call "one".
– Martin Argerami
Dec 15 '16 at 5:55
|
show 9 more comments
27
Seriously people what's with all the duplicates? Check and see if someone has already given your answer first!
– Noah Snyder
Jul 20 '10 at 20:28
78
Let me say a word about why 1/3 = .33333... is not obvious at all. What does it mean to say that some number is 1/3? Well division is the operation that undoes multiplication, so it means that it's a number that when you multiply by 3 you get 1. Well what happens when you multiply .3333... times 3? You get .9999... So unless you already know that .99999...=1 then you can't prove that 1/3 = .3333... The fact that .9999...=1 is more basic than the fact that 1/3 = .33333....!
– Noah Snyder
Jul 20 '10 at 21:32
11
Between any two different numbers, there is always another number between them. there is no number between 0.999... and 1
– Joao
Apr 28 '14 at 3:07
4
New prospective answerers, please heed Noah Snyder's comment from over five years ago. It's all the more valuable now.
– Brian Tung
Jan 15 '16 at 23:12
2
@BT: yes, it is a real number, and the question is not meaningless nor stupid. The number $0.999cdots $ is a perfectly well-defined real number: $sum_{k=1}^infty frac9 {10^k}$. It just happens to be the real number that we usually call "one".
– Martin Argerami
Dec 15 '16 at 5:55
27
27
Seriously people what's with all the duplicates? Check and see if someone has already given your answer first!
– Noah Snyder
Jul 20 '10 at 20:28
Seriously people what's with all the duplicates? Check and see if someone has already given your answer first!
– Noah Snyder
Jul 20 '10 at 20:28
78
78
Let me say a word about why 1/3 = .33333... is not obvious at all. What does it mean to say that some number is 1/3? Well division is the operation that undoes multiplication, so it means that it's a number that when you multiply by 3 you get 1. Well what happens when you multiply .3333... times 3? You get .9999... So unless you already know that .99999...=1 then you can't prove that 1/3 = .3333... The fact that .9999...=1 is more basic than the fact that 1/3 = .33333....!
– Noah Snyder
Jul 20 '10 at 21:32
Let me say a word about why 1/3 = .33333... is not obvious at all. What does it mean to say that some number is 1/3? Well division is the operation that undoes multiplication, so it means that it's a number that when you multiply by 3 you get 1. Well what happens when you multiply .3333... times 3? You get .9999... So unless you already know that .99999...=1 then you can't prove that 1/3 = .3333... The fact that .9999...=1 is more basic than the fact that 1/3 = .33333....!
– Noah Snyder
Jul 20 '10 at 21:32
11
11
Between any two different numbers, there is always another number between them. there is no number between 0.999... and 1
– Joao
Apr 28 '14 at 3:07
Between any two different numbers, there is always another number between them. there is no number between 0.999... and 1
– Joao
Apr 28 '14 at 3:07
4
4
New prospective answerers, please heed Noah Snyder's comment from over five years ago. It's all the more valuable now.
– Brian Tung
Jan 15 '16 at 23:12
New prospective answerers, please heed Noah Snyder's comment from over five years ago. It's all the more valuable now.
– Brian Tung
Jan 15 '16 at 23:12
2
2
@BT: yes, it is a real number, and the question is not meaningless nor stupid. The number $0.999cdots $ is a perfectly well-defined real number: $sum_{k=1}^infty frac9 {10^k}$. It just happens to be the real number that we usually call "one".
– Martin Argerami
Dec 15 '16 at 5:55
@BT: yes, it is a real number, and the question is not meaningless nor stupid. The number $0.999cdots $ is a perfectly well-defined real number: $sum_{k=1}^infty frac9 {10^k}$. It just happens to be the real number that we usually call "one".
– Martin Argerami
Dec 15 '16 at 5:55
|
show 9 more comments
25 Answers
25
active
oldest
votes
up vote
341
down vote
accepted
What does it mean when you refer to $.99999ldots$? Symbols don't mean anything in particular until you've defined what you mean by them.
In this case the definition is that you are taking the limit of $.9$, $.99$, $.999$, $.9999$, etc. What does it mean to say that limit is $1$? Well, it means that no matter how small a number $x$ you pick, I can show you a point in that sequence such that all further numbers in the sequence are within distance $x$ of $1$. But certainly whatever number you choose your number is bigger than $10^{-k}$ for some $k$. So I can just pick my point to be the $k$th spot in the sequence.
A more intuitive way of explaining the above argument is that the reason $.99999ldots = 1$ is that their difference is zero. So let's subtract $1.0000ldots -.99999ldots = .00000ldots = 0$. That is,
$1.0 -.9 = .1$
$1.00-.99 = .01$
$1.000-.999=.001$,
$ldots$
$1.000ldots -.99999ldots = .000ldots = 0$
78
Finite ones do, but infinite ones don't! The whole reason that this question confuses people is that defining what an infinite decimal means is difficult and confusing!
– Noah Snyder
Jul 20 '10 at 20:23
15
I think it's pretty standard to define infinite decimals as the infinite series where the terms are the individual digits divided by the appropriate power of the base. That is, 0.99999... = 9/10 + 9/10^2 + 9/10^3 + ...
– Isaac
Jul 20 '10 at 20:57
18
But that's exactly my point, taking the limit of series (and in fact, determining when such a limit exists) is a difficult and confusing concept!
– Noah Snyder
Jul 20 '10 at 21:30
38
@Doug: I don't understand what you're talking about. Could you try to clarify? What do you mean by an infinite sum if you don't mean the limit of the partial sums?
– Noah Snyder
Jul 23 '10 at 3:07
16
@Doug: Then your reading is incorrect.
– user126
Aug 17 '10 at 22:14
|
show 15 more comments
up vote
251
down vote
Suppose this was not the case, i.e. $0.9999... neq 1$. Then $0.9999... < 1$ (I hope we agree on that). But between two distinct real numbers, there's always another one (say $x$) in between, hence $0.9999... < x < 1$.
The decimal representation of $x$ must have a digit somewhere that is not $9$ (otherwise $x = 0.9999...$). But that means it's actually smaller, $x < 0.9999...$, contradicting the definition of $x$.
Thus, the assumption that there's a number between $0.9999...$ and $1$ is false, hence they're equal.
56
This proof also relies on the assumption that every real number can be represented by a (potentially infinite) decimal, which might or might not be accepted by someone asking the original question.
– bryn
Jul 22 '10 at 2:21
5
@bryn, this proof relies on a further assumption that the OP had specifically real numbers in mind when he asked the question.
– Mikhail Katz
Nov 25 '13 at 17:12
24
@BogdanAlexandru $frac{x+y}{2}$ is a number between $x$ and $y$
– Holographer
Sep 1 '14 at 15:39
3
$negneg Pimplies P$, yikes.
– Nikolaj-K
Nov 27 '15 at 3:06
3
@cat: Not completely sure what you mean, but see Double negative elimination and Constructive logic.
– Nikolaj-K
May 30 '16 at 21:31
|
show 3 more comments
up vote
163
down vote
What I really don't like about all the above answers, is the underlying assumption that $1/3=0.3333ldots$ How do you know that? It seems to me like assuming the something which is already known.
A proof I really like is:
$$begin{align}
0.9999ldots × 10 &= 9.9999ldots\
0.9999ldots × (9+1) &= 9.9999ldots\
text{by distribution rule: }Space{15ex}{0ex}{0ex} \
0.9999ldots × 9 + 0.9999ldots × 1 &= 9.9999ldots\
0.9999ldots × 9 &= 9.9999dots-0.9999ldots\
0.9999ldots × 9 &= 9\
0.9999ldots &= 1
end{align}$$
The only things I need to assume is, that $9.999ldots - 0.999ldots = 9$ and that $0.999ldots × 10 = 9.999ldots$ These seems to me intuitive enough to take for granted.
The proof is from an old high school level math book of the Open University in Israel.
10
0.9999... x 9 = 8.999999...
– Sklivvz
May 3 '11 at 20:51
4
@Sklivvz, true, since 8.999....=9. Did you have trouble understanding the algebra I did?
– Elazar Leibovich
May 4 '11 at 5:55
11
Sklivvz, but my answer does not rely on the fact that 8.999...=9, did it? Or am I missing something (tried to make it a bit more clear)
– Elazar Leibovich
May 4 '11 at 5:59
8
@Michael I never evaluate9*0.9999
at step 3 or at any step. I leave the expression as it is, and then use the fact that if9x=9
thenx=1
in the last step.
– Elazar Leibovich
Feb 17 '14 at 9:00
2
BTW, the first sentence referring to "all the above answers" does not apply (and has not applied for most of the time this answer has been up), because (in the default view at least) none of them assume that $1/3 = 0.333dots$.
– ShreevatsaR
Jul 20 '14 at 17:41
|
show 17 more comments
up vote
149
down vote
Assuming:
- infinite decimals are series where the terms are the digits divided by the proper power of the base
- the infinite geometric series $a + a cdot r + a cdot r^2 + a cdot r^3 + cdots$ has sum $dfrac{a}{1 - r}$ as long as $|r|<1$
$$0.99999ldots = frac{9}{10} + frac{9}{10^2} + frac{9}{10^3} + cdots$$
This is the infinite geometric series with first term $a = frac{9}{10}$ and common ratio $r = frac{1}{10}$, so it has sum $$frac{frac{9}{10}}{1 - frac{1}{10}} = frac{frac{9}{10}}{frac{9}{10}} = 1.$$
9
Your method is a simple way of converting the decimal representation of a rational number into a fraction, e.g. $0.150150150...=sum_{ngeq 1}frac{150}{10^{3n}}=frac{0.150}{1-10^{-3}}=frac{50}{333}$
– Américo Tavares
Aug 16 '10 at 22:02
The question is where are you getting this common ratio of 1/10 and what law permits you to use it in this case?
– Serj Sagan
Aug 2 '16 at 19:11
@SerjSagan Generally, when not otherwise indicated, numbers are written in base 10. That makes the ratio of the values of successive "places" 10 or $frac{1}{10}$, depending on direction. This is the "... proper power of the base" piece of my point 1.
– Isaac
Aug 2 '16 at 19:17
add a comment |
up vote
68
down vote
$$x=0.999...$$
$$10x=9.999...$$
$$10x-x=9.999...-0.999...$$
$$9x=9$$
$$x=1$$
thus, $0.999...=1$
1
This is the most intuitive argument, although some might say "But 10x-x isn't 9, because there's going to be a mismatch all the way to the right" - Noah's more complex deals with that.
– Charles Stewart
Jul 21 '10 at 10:55
10x - x != 9. 10x - x would be 8.9999...1. However infinite the extent of 9s is in x, if we multiply it by 10, the nines are shifted left by one position and a zero inserted at the "last" place, and then when you subtract the other number there is a nine subtracted from a zero at the far right. Otherwise we'd have to give 0.999.. some unusual properties like automatically increasing the number of nines when it is multiplied. It would not be just an ordinary number. Maybe that's the problem. 0.999... might just not be an ordinary type number as some people are using it.
– Doug Treadwell
Jul 23 '10 at 2:19
8
@Doug It's incorrect to talk about the "number of nines" because infinity minus a number = infinity. Infinity is transcendent. It means "uncountable". If you take infinity and slide it left a little bit, it's still infinity long.
– ErikE
Sep 25 '10 at 7:00
The problem is the assumption that9x = 9
when in fact9x = 8.999...
your proof is flawed.
– Serj Sagan
Aug 2 '16 at 19:16
9
@SerjSagan that line isn't an assumption, it's a deduction. If you believe that $9.999dots - 0.999dots = 9$, then you must therefore believe that $9x = 9$.
– Omnomnomnom
Dec 15 '16 at 17:03
|
show 1 more comment
up vote
52
down vote
Okay I burned a lot of reputation points (at least for me) on MathOverflow to gain clarity on how to give some intuition into this problem, so hopefully this answer will be at least be somewhat illuminating.
To gain a deeper understanding of what is going on, first we need to answer the question, "What is a number?"
There are a lot of ways to define numbers, but in general numbers are thought of as symbols that represent sets.
This is easy for things like the natural numbers. So 10 would correspond to the set with ten things -- like a bag of ten stones. Pretty straight forward.
The tricky part is that when we consider ten a subset of the real numbers, we actually redefine it. This is not emphasized even in higher mathematics classes, like real analysis; it just happens when we define the real numbers.
So what is 10 when constructed in the real numbers? Well, at least with the Dedekind cut version of the real numbers, all real numbers correspond to a set with an infinite amount of elements. This makes 10 under the hood look drastically different, although in practice it operates exactly the same.
So let's return to the question: Why is 10 the same as 9.99999? Because the real numbers have this completely surprising quality, where there is no next real number. So when you have two real numbers that are as close together as possible, they are the same. I can't think of any physical object that has this quality, but it's how the real numbers work (makes "real" seem ironic).
With integers (bag of stones version) this is not the same. When you have two integers as close to each other as possible they are still different, and they are distance one apart.
Put another way, 10 bag of stones are not the same as 9.9999999 but 10 the natural number, where natural numbers are a subset of the real numbers is.
The bottom line is that the real numbers have these tricky edge cases that are hard to understand intuitively. Don't worry, your intuition is not really failing you. :)
I didn't feel confident answering until I got this Terence Tao link:
(Wayback Machine) https://web.archive.org/web/20100725014132/http://www.google.com:80/buzz/114134834346472219368/RarPutThCJv/In-the-foundations-of-mathematics-the-standard
(PDF, page 12) https://terrytao.files.wordpress.com/2011/06/blog-book.pdf
4
The link doesn't work.
– user 170039
Jan 5 '16 at 15:08
I'm not sure that most people think of real numbers as representing sets. Indeed, probably few of those who didn't study mathematics or attend mathematics lectures have even heard of the Dedekind construction. The common visualization of real numbers is as points on a line.
– celtschk
Aug 14 '16 at 9:03
2
the link is dead
– baxx
Sep 10 '16 at 20:43
As a smart person, I actually like this answer better than balpha and Elezar Laibovich's answer. It's good enough for me because I can figure out from it a fuller answer that explains how people were looking for a definition of a real number in ZF such that the set of all of them is a complete ordered field so they found one and proved it's a complete ordered field. math.stackexchange.com/questions/2437893/… actually says what a real natural number is. Those answers aren't bad either because I can prove that all real numbers have a decimal representation.
– Timothy
May 17 at 1:34
add a comment |
up vote
42
down vote
There are genuine conceptual difficulties implicit in this question. The transition from the rational numbers to the real numbers is a difficult one, and it took a long time and a lot of thought to make it truly rigorous. It has been pointed out in other answers that the notation $0.999999ldots$ is just a shorthand notation for the infinite geometric series $sumlimits_{n=1}^{infty} 9left( frac{1}{10} right)^{n},$ which has sum $1.$ This is factually correct, but still sweeps some of the conceptual questions under the carpet. There are questions to be addressed about what we mean when we write down (or pretend to) an infinite decimal, or an infinite series. Either of those devices is just a shorthand notation which mathematicians agree will represent some numbers, given a set of ground rules. Let me try to present an argument to suggest that if the notation $0.99999ldots$ is to meaningfully represent any real number, then that number could be nothing other than the real number $1$, if we can agree that some truths are "self-evident".
Surely we can agree that the real number it represents can't be strictly greater than $1$, if it does indeed represent a real number. Let's now convince ourselves that it can't be a real number strictly less than $1,$
if it makes any sense at all. Well, if it was a real number $r < 1,$ that real number would be greater than or equal to $sumlimits_{n=1}^{k} 9left( frac{1}{10} right)^{n}$ for any finite integer $k.$ This last number is the decimal $0.99 ldots 9 $ which terminates after $k$ occurrences of $9,$ and differs from $1$ by $frac{1}{10^{k}}.$ Since $0 < r <1,$ there is a value of $k$ such that $frac{1}{10^{k}} < 1-r,$ so $1 - frac{1}{10^{k}} >r.$ Hence $sumlimits_{n=1}^{k} 9left( frac{1}{10} right)^{n} > r.$ But this can't be, because we agreed that $r$ should be greater than or equal to each of those truncated sums.
Have I proved that the recurring decimal is equal to $1$? Not really- what I have proved is that if we allow that recurring decimal to meaningfully represent any real number, that real number has to be $1,$ since it can't be strictly less than $1$ and can't be strictly greater than $1$. At this point, it becomes a matter of convention to agree that the real number $1$ can be represented in that form, and that convention will be consistent with our usual operations with real numbers and ordering of the real numbers, and equating the expression with any other real number would not maintain that consistency.
5
This is the best answer here; it's a shame it was posted four years later so it's gotten so little attention.
– Eric Wofsey
Oct 4 '15 at 0:44
1
If I am not mistaken then this answer also answers the question of this post.
– user 170039
Jan 6 '16 at 14:32
By the way, I was thinking that maybe you could write an answer for the linked post as well (or else, can you just tell me how can I give a link to this answer in a comment below my post?).
– user 170039
Jan 6 '16 at 14:40
1
I'm not sure how to set up links on here ( maybe the "cite") button. I am basically agreeing with what you say in your post.
– Geoff Robinson
Jan 6 '16 at 15:03
I think that the "evident" issue of a number being an abstract concept existing in isolation from any positional representation should also be explicitly stated. One then proceeds to give rules as to how the positional representation works (as you did), and from these rules it follows that all real numbers have an infinitely long representation in any base, and rational numbers have a finitely long representation in some bases. The integers are a special case of rational numbers that have a finite representation in all bases.
– Kuba Ober
Jul 28 '16 at 19:55
add a comment |
up vote
39
down vote
One argument against this is that 0.99999999... is "somewhat" less than 1. How much exactly?
1 - 0.999999... = ε (0)
If the above is true, the following also must be true:
9 × (1 - 0.999999...) = ε × 9
Let's calculate:
0.999... ×
9 =
───────────
8.1
81
81
.
.
.
───────────
8.999...
Thus:
9 - 8.999999... = 9ε (1)
But:
8.999999... = 8 + 0.99999... (2)
Indeed:
8.00000000... +
0.99999999... =
────────────────
8.99999999...
Now let's see what we can deduce from (0)
, (1)
and (2)
.
9 - 8.999999... = 9ε because of (2)
9 - 8.999999... = 9 - (8 + 0.99999...) = because of (1)
= 9 - 8 - (1 - ε) because of (0)
= 1 - 1 + ε
= ε.
Thus:
9ε = ε
8ε = 0
ε = 0
1 - 0.999999... = ε = 0
Quod erat demonstrandum. Pardon my unicode.
I did my best to avoid0.00000...
, but this made the calculations not as strikingly simple as I'd have liked to.
– badp
Jul 20 '10 at 21:10
Why was this voted down? It seems reasonable to this amateur math enjoyer.
– ErikE
Sep 25 '10 at 7:07
@Emtucifor I guess this sounds like "nonsense" to people that disagree on the basic premise of0.999... = 1
:)
– badp
Sep 25 '10 at 7:21
8ε = 0 instead of 10ε = 0
– user59671
May 9 '13 at 9:37
2
@SerjSagan nope, the RHS of (1) follows from (0). The fact that $9ε = ε$ is precisely the point I'm making.
– badp
Aug 2 '16 at 20:00
|
show 9 more comments
up vote
23
down vote
.999... = 1
because .999...
is a concise symbolic representation of "the limit of some variable as it approaches one." Therefore, .999... = 1
for the same reason the limit of x as x approaches 1 equals 1.
add a comment |
up vote
18
down vote
If you take two real numbers x
and y
then there per definition of the real number z
for which x < z < y
or x > z > y
is true.
For x = 0.99999...
and y = 1
you can't find a z
and therefore 0.99999... = 1
.
add a comment |
up vote
15
down vote
You can visualise it by thinking about it in infinitesimals. The more $9's$ you have on the end of $0.999$, the closer you get to $1$. When you add an infinite number of $9's$ to the decimal expansion, you are infinitely close to $1$ (or an infinitesimal distance away).
And this isn't a rigorous proof, just an aid to visualisation of the result.
I think this answer is not needed. It's similar to another answer but has wrong information. Infinitesimal numbers exist only in the hyperreal number system and in the hyperreal system, numbers infinitesimally close are not equal. The real numbers are a subset of the hyperreal numbers so the community decided theat the notation represents 1 and not a number infinitesimally close because then it wouldn't represent a real number. Maybe the real numbers can be defined as equivalence classes infinitesimally close hyperreal numbers and from that, redefine the notation to represent the number 1.
– Timothy
May 22 at 19:19
add a comment |
up vote
12
down vote
Indeed this is true. The underlying reason is that decimal numbers are not unique representations of the reals. (Technically, there does not exist a bijection between the set of all decimal numbers and the reals.)
Here's a very simple proof:
$$begin{align}
frac13&=0.333ldots&hbox{(by long division)}\
implies0.333ldotstimes3&=0.999ldots&hbox{(multiplying each digit by $3$)}
end{align}$$
Then we already know $0.333ldotstimes3=1$ therefore $0.999ldots=1$.
22
-1. This is not a proof at all! Why is 1/3=0.333...? Seriously folks, for the private beta, let's try to maintain a little correctiness.
– Scott Morrison
Jul 20 '10 at 20:03
5
@Scott: Sure it is. You can prove it easily by long division. This is about algorithms for mathematical methods really.
– Noldorin
Jul 20 '10 at 20:12
6
@Scott: Might help to stop whining and post what you think is the 'correct' answer then.
– Noldorin
Jul 20 '10 at 20:17
11
Just to nitpick, there is a bijection between the set of decimal expansions and reals because they are sets with the same cardinality. It's just that the natural map taking expansions to real numbers isn't injective.
– Simon Nickerson
Jul 20 '10 at 21:15
3
@Scott, I see it would not be obvious that 1/3=0.333..., but as by Noldorins comment regarding long division, what would be wrong with this as a proof, if the first line is annotated with 'by long division' ?
– Sami
Jul 21 '10 at 4:58
|
show 11 more comments
up vote
11
down vote
Given (by long division):
$frac{1}{3} = 0.bar{3}$
Multiply by 3:
$3times left( frac{1}{3} right) = left( 0.bar{3} right) times 3$
Therefore:
$frac{3}{3} = 0.bar{9}$
QED.
I think the long division precisely involves the proof of a limit like the sum mentioned above...
– C-Star-Puppy
Aug 27 '14 at 21:07
1
@FreeziiS, for this particular question the fact of a rigorous proof happens to be less important than the fact of a convincing proof. Plenty of people trust the long division algorithm because they learned it in school; they haven't seen a rigorous proof for its workability because they don't care; it obviously works. It is these people (who don't care about or trust rigorous proofs) who argue the most about $0.999999...$
– Wildcard
Dec 20 '16 at 0:16
add a comment |
up vote
9
down vote
Often times people who ask this question are not very convinced by a proof. Since they may not be particularly math inclined, they may feel that a proof is a sort of sleight-of-hand trick, and I find the following intuitive argument (read "don't down-vote me for lack of rigor, lack of rigor is the point") a bit more convincing:
STEP 1) If $.99...neq1$, everyone agrees that it must be less than $1$. Let $alpha$ denote $.99...$, this mysterious number less than $1$.
STEP 2) Using a number line, you can convince them that since $alpha<1$, there must be another number $beta$ such that $alpha<beta<1$.
STEP 3) Since $alpha<beta$, one of the digits of $beta$ must be bigger than the corresponding digit of $alpha$.
STEP 4) However it is usually intitively clear that you cannot make any digit of $.99...$ bigger without making the resulting number (ie $beta$) bigger than $1$.
STEP 5) Thus no such $beta$ can exist, and thus $.99...$ cannot be less than $1$.
add a comment |
up vote
7
down vote
The real number system is defined as an extension of the rationals with the property that any sequence with an upper bound has a LEAST upper bound. The expression " 0.9-repeated" is defined to be the least real-number upper bound of the sequence 0.9. 0.99, 0.999,..... , which is 1. The rationals (and the reals) can also be extended to an arithmetic system (an ordered field) in which there are positive values which are less than every positive rational. In such systems the expression ".9-repeated" has no meaning.
add a comment |
up vote
7
down vote
The problem isn't proving that $0.9999... = 1$. There are many proofs and they all are easy.
The problem is being convinced that every argument you are making actually is valid and makes sense, and not having a sinking feeling you aren't just falling for some parlor trick.
$0.99...9;$ (with $n$ 9s) is $sum_{i= 1}^n frac 9 {10^i}$ so "obviously" $0.999....$ (with an infinite number of 9s) is $sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac 9{10^i}$.
The obvious objection is: does it even make sense to talk about adding an infinite number of terms? How can we talk about taking and adding an infinite number of terms?
And it's a legitimate objection.
So when we learn math in elementary school we are told: Every real number can be written as a decimal expansion (maybe infinite) and every possible decimal expansion is a real number. And this is true. But we are not told why and we are expected to take it on faith, and we usually do.
IF we take this on faith then a proof is very easy:
$0.9999.... = sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac 9{10^i}$
$10*(0.9999....) = 10*sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac 9{10^i}= sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac {90}{10^i}=$
$sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac 9{10^{i-1}} = 9/10^0 + sum_{i = 2}^{infty} frac 9{10^{i-1}}= 9 + sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac 9{10^i}$ (Look at the indexes!)
So...
$10*(0.999...) - (0.9999...) = (10 - 1)*0.9999.... = 9*0.99999.... = $
$9 + sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac 9{10^i} - sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac 9{10^i} = 9$.
So...
$0.9999.... = 9/9 = 1$.
Easy! !!!!!!!IF!!!!!!! we take it on faith that: Every real number can be written as a decimal expansion (maybe infinite) and every possible decimal expansion is a real number.
So why can we take that on faith? That's the issue: why is that true and what does it mean?
So....
We've got the Integers. We use them to count discrete measurements. We can use an integer to divide a unit 1 into $m$ sub-units to measure measurements of $1/m$. As the $m$ can be as large as we want the $1/m$ can be as precise as we want and the system of all possible $n/m; m ne 0$ can measure any possible quantity with arbitrary and infinite precision.
We hope. We call these $n/m$ numbers the Rationals and everything is fine until we discover that we can't actually measure measurements such as the square root of two or pi.
But the Rationals still have infinite precision. We can get within 1/10 away from pi. We can get within 1/100 away from pi. Within $1/10^n$ for any possible power of 10.
At this point, we hope we can say "we can't measure it with any finite power of 10 but we can always go one more significant measure, so if we go through infinite powers of 10 we will measure it to precision" and we hope that explanation will be convincing.
But it isn't really. We have these "missing numbers" and we can get infinitely close the them, but what are they really?
Well, we decide to become math majors and in our senior year of college we take a Real Analysis course and we find out.
We can view numbers as sets of rational numbers. We can split the rational numbers at any point into two sets. We can split the rational numbers so that all the rational numbers less than 1/2 are in set A and all the rational numbers greater than or equal to 1/2 are in set B (which we ignore; we are only interested in set A.)
These "cuts" can occur at any point but they must follow the following rules:
--the set A of all the smaller rational numbers is not empty. Nor does it contain every rational number. Some rational number is not in it.
--if any rational number (call it q) is in A, then every rational number smaller than q is also in A. (This means that if r is a rational not in A, then every rational bigger than r is also not in A.)
-- A does not have a single largest element. (So it can be all the elements less than 1/2 but it can't be all the elements less than or equal to 1/2).
And we let $overline R$ be the collection of all possible ways to "cut" the rational numbers in half that way.
Notice sometimes the cut will occur at a rational number (all the rationals less than 1/2), but sometimes it will occur at points "between" the rational numbers. (All the rationals whose squares are less than 2). So the collection $overline R$ is a larger set than the set of Rational numbers.
It turns out we can define the Real numbers as the points of $overline R$ where we can cut the rationals in two.
We need to do a bit or work to show that this is actually a number system. We say $x, y in overline R; x < y$ if the "Set A made by cutting at x" $subset$ "Set A made by cutting at y". And we say $x + y = $ the point where we need to cut so that the set A created contains all the sums of the two other sets created by cutting at x and y. And we have to prove math works on $overline R$. But we can do it. And we do.
But as a consequence we see that every real number is the least upper bound limit of a sequence of rational numbers. That's pretty much the definition of what a "cut point" is; the point that separate all the rationals less than it from all the other rationals.
I like to say (somewhat trivially) that: the real number $x$ is the least upper bound of all the rational numbers that are smaller than $x$. And it's true!
In the real numbers, every real number is the limit of some sequence of rational numbers. And every bounded sequence of rational numbers will have a real number least upper bound limit.
...
Let that sink in for a minute.
=====
Okay, so given a sequence {3, 3.1, 3.14, 3.141,....} = {finite decimals that are less than pi} is a bounded sequence of rational numbers so $pi = $ the limit of the sequence which is also the limit of the infinite sequence 3.1415926....
It now makes sense to talk of $0.9999.... = sum_{i=1}^{infty}9/10^i = lim{sum_{i=1}^n9/10^i}$ = a precise and real number.
And from there we can say with confidence that that number is $1$. (By any of these proofs.)
add a comment |
up vote
6
down vote
Another approach is the following:
$$begin{align}
0.overline9 &=lim_{n to infty} 0.underbrace{99dots 9}_{ntext{ times}} \
&= lim_{n to infty} sumlimits_{k=1}^n frac{9}{10^k} \
&=lim_{n to infty} 1-frac{1}{10^n} \
&=1-lim_{n to infty} frac{1}{10^n} \
&=1.
end{align}$$
7
This approach appears in Isaac's answer from 4 years earlier.
– Jonas Meyer
Aug 26 '14 at 2:15
add a comment |
up vote
5
down vote
There are some situations in which something like $0.99999ldots < 1$ indeed holds. Here is one coming from social choice theory.
Let $w_1>w_2>ldots$ be an infinite sequence of positive numbers, and let $T$ be a number in the range $(0,sum_i w_i)$. Pick an index $i$. Choose a random permutation $pi$ of the positive integers, and consider the running totals
$$
w_{pi(1)}, w_{pi(1)} + w_{pi(2)}, w_{pi(1)} + w_{pi(2)} + w_{pi(3)}, cdots
$$
The Shapley value $varphi_i(T)$ is the probability that the first time that the running total exceeds $T$ is when $w_i$ is added.
We will particularly be interested in the case in which the sequence $w_i$ is super-increasing: for each $i$, $w_i geq sum_{j=i+1}^infty w_j$. The simplest case is $w_i = 2^{-i}$. Every number $T in (0,1)$ can be written in the form
$$ T = 2^{-a_0} + 2^{-a_1} + cdots, qquad a_0 < a_1 < cdots. $$
In this case we can give an explicit formula for $varphi_i(T)$:
$$
varphi_i(T) = begin{cases}
sum_{tcolon a_t>i} frac{1}{a_t binom{a_t-1}{t}} & text{if } i notin {a_0,a_1,ldots}, \
frac{1}{a_s binom{a_s-1}{s}} - sum_{tcolon a_t>i} frac{1}{a_t binom{a_t-1}{t-1}} & text{if } i = a_s.
end{cases}
$$
The first two functions are plotted here:
What happens for different sets of weights? The same formula applies, for
$$
T = w_{a_0} + w_{a_1} + cdots, qquad a_0 < a_1 < cdots.
$$
In general not all $T$ will be of this form; for $T$ not of this form, we take the lowest upper bound which is of this form. What we get for $w_i = 3^{-i}$ is:
Notice all the horizontal parts, for example the blue line at $y=1$ at $x in (1/6,1/3)$. Where does this stem from? Note that $1/3 = 3^{-1} = w_1$, whereas $1/6 = sum_{i=2}^infty 3^{-i} = sum_{i=2}^infty w_i$. If we substitute $w_i = 2^{-i}$, then $1/3$ corresponds to $0.1$ (in binary), whereas $1/6$ corresponds to $0.011111ldots$. So in this case there is a (visible) gap between $0.011111ldots$ and $0.1$!
For more, take a look at this question and this manuscript.
add a comment |
up vote
4
down vote
One cool way I learned to prove this is that, assuming by $0.99999...$ you mean $0.bar{9}$. Well we can say that
$$0.bar{9}=sum_{n=1}^{infty}9cdot 10^{-n}=9sum_{n=1}^{infty}frac{1}{10^n}$$
Which we know converges by fact that this is a geometric series with the ratio between terms being less than $1$. So we know that
$$9sum_{n=1}^{infty}frac{1}{10^n}=9left(frac{1}{1-frac{1}{10}}-1right)=10-9=1$$
Note that we subtract off the $1$ in the parentheses because we started indexing at $1$ rather than at $0$, so we have to subtract of the value of the sequence at $n=0$ which is $1$.
2
"Which we know converges by fact that this is a geometric series with the ratio between terms being less than 1." I don't think anyone who does know this would be questioning whether .9999.... = 1. The only people who are confused on the concept most assuredly do not know this.
– fleablood
Jan 15 '16 at 20:03
Just because you have studied series doesn't mean you have seen this proof. Hence why I have added it as a wiki answer on such a highly up voted answer, which people visiting it do not necessary have the same mathematical knowledge as the OP.
– Will Fisher
Jan 15 '16 at 21:55
add a comment |
up vote
3
down vote
Here's my favorite reason why $.999ldots$ should equal $1$:$^{*}$
begin{align*}
.999ldots + .999ldots
&= (.9 + .09 + .009 + cdots) + (.9 + .09 + .009 + cdots) \
&= (.9 + .9) + (.09 + .09) + (.009 + .009) + cdots \
&= 1.8 + .18 + .018 + .0018 + cdots \
&= (1 + .8) + (.1 + .08) + (.01 + .008) + (.001 + .0008) + cdots \
&= 1 + (.8 + .1) + (.08 + .01) + (.008 + .001) + cdots \
&= 1 + .9 + .09 + .009 + cdots \
&= 1 + .999ldots
end{align*}
It follows subtracting $.999ldots$ from both sides that $.999ldots = 1$.
The reason I like this explanation best is that addition of (positive) infinite decimal expansions (defined in a particular way) is both commutative and associative even if you insist that $.999ldots$ and $1$ are different numbers. That is, it forms a commutative monoid.
But the cancellation property fails: if $a + b = a + c$, then we can't necessarily conclude $b = c$. The example of this is above, and the most fundamental reason why $.999ldots = 1$ is arguably so that the cancellation property can hold.
$^{*}$The calculation given here (using rearrangmenet and regrouping of terms) is informal, and not intended to be a proof, but rather to give some idea of how you can add infinite decimal expansions in the monoid where $.999ldots ne 1$. It does end up being true that $.999ldots + .999ldots = 1 + .999ldots$ in this monoid.
2
It doesn't feel convincing to me to assume that blithely that you can rearrange the infinite sums the way you do here, without changing their value. It is true that it is safe in this particular case, but I don't see how one can show that except by developing enough of a theory of limits that we might as well just sum $sum_{n=1}^infty 9/10^n$ directly.
– Henning Makholm
Jul 17 '16 at 2:46
@HenningMakholm Right--it's not a convincing proof that $.999ldots = 1$ unless you accept that infinite sums of real numbers can be rearranged and regrouped in any way (which is true of course but much more nontrivial than the basic result that the limit of $.999ldots$ is $1$).
– 6005
Jul 17 '16 at 4:19
My actual point is that you can define the addition of infinite expansions even while you insist that $.999ldots ne 1$, and if you do so (although I don't give the definition) you get $.999ldots + .999ldots = 1 + .999ldots$. The aligned equation is just informal rearrangements but is intended to sort of show how the definition of addition of infinite decimal expansions would work, in this case at least.
– 6005
Jul 17 '16 at 4:20
1
It is not true in general that "infinite sums of real numbers can be rearranged and regrouped in any way". It works in this particular case because all of the terms being rearranged are all positive -- but in order to argue that this is safer than the general case (rearranging a conditionally convergent series such as $sum frac{(-1)^n}{n}$ fails spectacularly) it seems that you need to develop so much material that you cannot really keep open an option for $0.999...$ to differ from $1$.
– Henning Makholm
Jul 17 '16 at 9:12
@HenningMakholm Oh I'm sorry, that was a typo. Of course I'm aware. I meant positive real numbers.
– 6005
Jul 17 '16 at 14:43
|
show 1 more comment
up vote
3
down vote
Use the Squeeze Theorem:
$$0<1-0.999...=0.1+0.9-0.999...=0.1-0.0999...<0.1=0.1^1$$
$$0<0.1-0.0999...=0.01+0.09-0.0999...=0.01-0.00999...<0.01=0.1^2$$
$$...$$
$$0<1-0.999...<0.1^n$$
$$0le 1-0.999... le limlimits_{ntoinfty}0.1^n=0.$$
add a comment |
up vote
1
down vote
If we take a version of decimal notation with full complement it is indeed so.
In this system, instead of allowing $0.2$ and $0.1999...$ we restrict decimal notation to use only infinite version $0.19999...$ shortly written as $0.1overline{9}$
Simply, we do not allow an infinite trail of zeros.
In this system, there is no $0$ written as $0.000...$ instead it is $...999.999...$ or with our succinct notation $overline{9}.overline{9}$
Negative numbers are written in complement notation. For example, $...998.999...=overline{9}8.overline{9}=-1$
All rules of multiplication addition subtraction are totally valid.
In this system, it is indeed $0.99999...=0.overline{9}=1$ because we cannot represent $1$ as $1.0000...$.
add a comment |
up vote
0
down vote
The direct proof:
$$0.9999999999...=lim_{ntoinfty} left( 1-frac {1}{10^n}right)=1-0=1$$
Q.E.D.
add a comment |
up vote
0
down vote
If you allow a "decimal representation" of a number to end finally with period $9$ as in $0.bar9$ or $1.123bar9$ this "decimal representation "of a number would not be unique.
We know by definition that $0.bar9=sum_{n=1}^{infty}(9/10)^n=1$, but for the sake of the uniquenes of the decimal representation $0.bar9$ is not a decimal representation of any number.
add a comment |
up vote
-1
down vote
I can't help thinking that some of the people who aren't quite convinced by $0.33333 ... × 3$ might be happier considering multiples of $frac 19$ instead:
$frac{1}{9}=0.111111 . . .$
$frac{2}{9}=0.222222 . . .$
$frac{3}{9}=0.333333 . . .$
$frac{4}{9}=0.444444 . . .$
all the way up to
$frac{8}{9}=0.888888 . . .$
$frac{9}{9}=0.999999 . . .$
Somehow the consistent pattern helps. But there's still the psychological issue that because only finitely many digits are visible, 0.999999 . . . "feels smaller" than 1.000000 . . . while $frac 99$ doesn't.
add a comment |
protected by Alex Becker Mar 27 '14 at 2:58
Thank you for your interest in this question.
Because it has attracted low-quality or spam answers that had to be removed, posting an answer now requires 10 reputation on this site (the association bonus does not count).
Would you like to answer one of these unanswered questions instead?
25 Answers
25
active
oldest
votes
25 Answers
25
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
up vote
341
down vote
accepted
What does it mean when you refer to $.99999ldots$? Symbols don't mean anything in particular until you've defined what you mean by them.
In this case the definition is that you are taking the limit of $.9$, $.99$, $.999$, $.9999$, etc. What does it mean to say that limit is $1$? Well, it means that no matter how small a number $x$ you pick, I can show you a point in that sequence such that all further numbers in the sequence are within distance $x$ of $1$. But certainly whatever number you choose your number is bigger than $10^{-k}$ for some $k$. So I can just pick my point to be the $k$th spot in the sequence.
A more intuitive way of explaining the above argument is that the reason $.99999ldots = 1$ is that their difference is zero. So let's subtract $1.0000ldots -.99999ldots = .00000ldots = 0$. That is,
$1.0 -.9 = .1$
$1.00-.99 = .01$
$1.000-.999=.001$,
$ldots$
$1.000ldots -.99999ldots = .000ldots = 0$
78
Finite ones do, but infinite ones don't! The whole reason that this question confuses people is that defining what an infinite decimal means is difficult and confusing!
– Noah Snyder
Jul 20 '10 at 20:23
15
I think it's pretty standard to define infinite decimals as the infinite series where the terms are the individual digits divided by the appropriate power of the base. That is, 0.99999... = 9/10 + 9/10^2 + 9/10^3 + ...
– Isaac
Jul 20 '10 at 20:57
18
But that's exactly my point, taking the limit of series (and in fact, determining when such a limit exists) is a difficult and confusing concept!
– Noah Snyder
Jul 20 '10 at 21:30
38
@Doug: I don't understand what you're talking about. Could you try to clarify? What do you mean by an infinite sum if you don't mean the limit of the partial sums?
– Noah Snyder
Jul 23 '10 at 3:07
16
@Doug: Then your reading is incorrect.
– user126
Aug 17 '10 at 22:14
|
show 15 more comments
up vote
341
down vote
accepted
What does it mean when you refer to $.99999ldots$? Symbols don't mean anything in particular until you've defined what you mean by them.
In this case the definition is that you are taking the limit of $.9$, $.99$, $.999$, $.9999$, etc. What does it mean to say that limit is $1$? Well, it means that no matter how small a number $x$ you pick, I can show you a point in that sequence such that all further numbers in the sequence are within distance $x$ of $1$. But certainly whatever number you choose your number is bigger than $10^{-k}$ for some $k$. So I can just pick my point to be the $k$th spot in the sequence.
A more intuitive way of explaining the above argument is that the reason $.99999ldots = 1$ is that their difference is zero. So let's subtract $1.0000ldots -.99999ldots = .00000ldots = 0$. That is,
$1.0 -.9 = .1$
$1.00-.99 = .01$
$1.000-.999=.001$,
$ldots$
$1.000ldots -.99999ldots = .000ldots = 0$
78
Finite ones do, but infinite ones don't! The whole reason that this question confuses people is that defining what an infinite decimal means is difficult and confusing!
– Noah Snyder
Jul 20 '10 at 20:23
15
I think it's pretty standard to define infinite decimals as the infinite series where the terms are the individual digits divided by the appropriate power of the base. That is, 0.99999... = 9/10 + 9/10^2 + 9/10^3 + ...
– Isaac
Jul 20 '10 at 20:57
18
But that's exactly my point, taking the limit of series (and in fact, determining when such a limit exists) is a difficult and confusing concept!
– Noah Snyder
Jul 20 '10 at 21:30
38
@Doug: I don't understand what you're talking about. Could you try to clarify? What do you mean by an infinite sum if you don't mean the limit of the partial sums?
– Noah Snyder
Jul 23 '10 at 3:07
16
@Doug: Then your reading is incorrect.
– user126
Aug 17 '10 at 22:14
|
show 15 more comments
up vote
341
down vote
accepted
up vote
341
down vote
accepted
What does it mean when you refer to $.99999ldots$? Symbols don't mean anything in particular until you've defined what you mean by them.
In this case the definition is that you are taking the limit of $.9$, $.99$, $.999$, $.9999$, etc. What does it mean to say that limit is $1$? Well, it means that no matter how small a number $x$ you pick, I can show you a point in that sequence such that all further numbers in the sequence are within distance $x$ of $1$. But certainly whatever number you choose your number is bigger than $10^{-k}$ for some $k$. So I can just pick my point to be the $k$th spot in the sequence.
A more intuitive way of explaining the above argument is that the reason $.99999ldots = 1$ is that their difference is zero. So let's subtract $1.0000ldots -.99999ldots = .00000ldots = 0$. That is,
$1.0 -.9 = .1$
$1.00-.99 = .01$
$1.000-.999=.001$,
$ldots$
$1.000ldots -.99999ldots = .000ldots = 0$
What does it mean when you refer to $.99999ldots$? Symbols don't mean anything in particular until you've defined what you mean by them.
In this case the definition is that you are taking the limit of $.9$, $.99$, $.999$, $.9999$, etc. What does it mean to say that limit is $1$? Well, it means that no matter how small a number $x$ you pick, I can show you a point in that sequence such that all further numbers in the sequence are within distance $x$ of $1$. But certainly whatever number you choose your number is bigger than $10^{-k}$ for some $k$. So I can just pick my point to be the $k$th spot in the sequence.
A more intuitive way of explaining the above argument is that the reason $.99999ldots = 1$ is that their difference is zero. So let's subtract $1.0000ldots -.99999ldots = .00000ldots = 0$. That is,
$1.0 -.9 = .1$
$1.00-.99 = .01$
$1.000-.999=.001$,
$ldots$
$1.000ldots -.99999ldots = .000ldots = 0$
edited May 8 at 20:22
community wiki
6 revs, 6 users 62%
Noah Snyder
78
Finite ones do, but infinite ones don't! The whole reason that this question confuses people is that defining what an infinite decimal means is difficult and confusing!
– Noah Snyder
Jul 20 '10 at 20:23
15
I think it's pretty standard to define infinite decimals as the infinite series where the terms are the individual digits divided by the appropriate power of the base. That is, 0.99999... = 9/10 + 9/10^2 + 9/10^3 + ...
– Isaac
Jul 20 '10 at 20:57
18
But that's exactly my point, taking the limit of series (and in fact, determining when such a limit exists) is a difficult and confusing concept!
– Noah Snyder
Jul 20 '10 at 21:30
38
@Doug: I don't understand what you're talking about. Could you try to clarify? What do you mean by an infinite sum if you don't mean the limit of the partial sums?
– Noah Snyder
Jul 23 '10 at 3:07
16
@Doug: Then your reading is incorrect.
– user126
Aug 17 '10 at 22:14
|
show 15 more comments
78
Finite ones do, but infinite ones don't! The whole reason that this question confuses people is that defining what an infinite decimal means is difficult and confusing!
– Noah Snyder
Jul 20 '10 at 20:23
15
I think it's pretty standard to define infinite decimals as the infinite series where the terms are the individual digits divided by the appropriate power of the base. That is, 0.99999... = 9/10 + 9/10^2 + 9/10^3 + ...
– Isaac
Jul 20 '10 at 20:57
18
But that's exactly my point, taking the limit of series (and in fact, determining when such a limit exists) is a difficult and confusing concept!
– Noah Snyder
Jul 20 '10 at 21:30
38
@Doug: I don't understand what you're talking about. Could you try to clarify? What do you mean by an infinite sum if you don't mean the limit of the partial sums?
– Noah Snyder
Jul 23 '10 at 3:07
16
@Doug: Then your reading is incorrect.
– user126
Aug 17 '10 at 22:14
78
78
Finite ones do, but infinite ones don't! The whole reason that this question confuses people is that defining what an infinite decimal means is difficult and confusing!
– Noah Snyder
Jul 20 '10 at 20:23
Finite ones do, but infinite ones don't! The whole reason that this question confuses people is that defining what an infinite decimal means is difficult and confusing!
– Noah Snyder
Jul 20 '10 at 20:23
15
15
I think it's pretty standard to define infinite decimals as the infinite series where the terms are the individual digits divided by the appropriate power of the base. That is, 0.99999... = 9/10 + 9/10^2 + 9/10^3 + ...
– Isaac
Jul 20 '10 at 20:57
I think it's pretty standard to define infinite decimals as the infinite series where the terms are the individual digits divided by the appropriate power of the base. That is, 0.99999... = 9/10 + 9/10^2 + 9/10^3 + ...
– Isaac
Jul 20 '10 at 20:57
18
18
But that's exactly my point, taking the limit of series (and in fact, determining when such a limit exists) is a difficult and confusing concept!
– Noah Snyder
Jul 20 '10 at 21:30
But that's exactly my point, taking the limit of series (and in fact, determining when such a limit exists) is a difficult and confusing concept!
– Noah Snyder
Jul 20 '10 at 21:30
38
38
@Doug: I don't understand what you're talking about. Could you try to clarify? What do you mean by an infinite sum if you don't mean the limit of the partial sums?
– Noah Snyder
Jul 23 '10 at 3:07
@Doug: I don't understand what you're talking about. Could you try to clarify? What do you mean by an infinite sum if you don't mean the limit of the partial sums?
– Noah Snyder
Jul 23 '10 at 3:07
16
16
@Doug: Then your reading is incorrect.
– user126
Aug 17 '10 at 22:14
@Doug: Then your reading is incorrect.
– user126
Aug 17 '10 at 22:14
|
show 15 more comments
up vote
251
down vote
Suppose this was not the case, i.e. $0.9999... neq 1$. Then $0.9999... < 1$ (I hope we agree on that). But between two distinct real numbers, there's always another one (say $x$) in between, hence $0.9999... < x < 1$.
The decimal representation of $x$ must have a digit somewhere that is not $9$ (otherwise $x = 0.9999...$). But that means it's actually smaller, $x < 0.9999...$, contradicting the definition of $x$.
Thus, the assumption that there's a number between $0.9999...$ and $1$ is false, hence they're equal.
56
This proof also relies on the assumption that every real number can be represented by a (potentially infinite) decimal, which might or might not be accepted by someone asking the original question.
– bryn
Jul 22 '10 at 2:21
5
@bryn, this proof relies on a further assumption that the OP had specifically real numbers in mind when he asked the question.
– Mikhail Katz
Nov 25 '13 at 17:12
24
@BogdanAlexandru $frac{x+y}{2}$ is a number between $x$ and $y$
– Holographer
Sep 1 '14 at 15:39
3
$negneg Pimplies P$, yikes.
– Nikolaj-K
Nov 27 '15 at 3:06
3
@cat: Not completely sure what you mean, but see Double negative elimination and Constructive logic.
– Nikolaj-K
May 30 '16 at 21:31
|
show 3 more comments
up vote
251
down vote
Suppose this was not the case, i.e. $0.9999... neq 1$. Then $0.9999... < 1$ (I hope we agree on that). But between two distinct real numbers, there's always another one (say $x$) in between, hence $0.9999... < x < 1$.
The decimal representation of $x$ must have a digit somewhere that is not $9$ (otherwise $x = 0.9999...$). But that means it's actually smaller, $x < 0.9999...$, contradicting the definition of $x$.
Thus, the assumption that there's a number between $0.9999...$ and $1$ is false, hence they're equal.
56
This proof also relies on the assumption that every real number can be represented by a (potentially infinite) decimal, which might or might not be accepted by someone asking the original question.
– bryn
Jul 22 '10 at 2:21
5
@bryn, this proof relies on a further assumption that the OP had specifically real numbers in mind when he asked the question.
– Mikhail Katz
Nov 25 '13 at 17:12
24
@BogdanAlexandru $frac{x+y}{2}$ is a number between $x$ and $y$
– Holographer
Sep 1 '14 at 15:39
3
$negneg Pimplies P$, yikes.
– Nikolaj-K
Nov 27 '15 at 3:06
3
@cat: Not completely sure what you mean, but see Double negative elimination and Constructive logic.
– Nikolaj-K
May 30 '16 at 21:31
|
show 3 more comments
up vote
251
down vote
up vote
251
down vote
Suppose this was not the case, i.e. $0.9999... neq 1$. Then $0.9999... < 1$ (I hope we agree on that). But between two distinct real numbers, there's always another one (say $x$) in between, hence $0.9999... < x < 1$.
The decimal representation of $x$ must have a digit somewhere that is not $9$ (otherwise $x = 0.9999...$). But that means it's actually smaller, $x < 0.9999...$, contradicting the definition of $x$.
Thus, the assumption that there's a number between $0.9999...$ and $1$ is false, hence they're equal.
Suppose this was not the case, i.e. $0.9999... neq 1$. Then $0.9999... < 1$ (I hope we agree on that). But between two distinct real numbers, there's always another one (say $x$) in between, hence $0.9999... < x < 1$.
The decimal representation of $x$ must have a digit somewhere that is not $9$ (otherwise $x = 0.9999...$). But that means it's actually smaller, $x < 0.9999...$, contradicting the definition of $x$.
Thus, the assumption that there's a number between $0.9999...$ and $1$ is false, hence they're equal.
edited Dec 15 '16 at 20:28
community wiki
4 revs, 4 users 57%
balpha
56
This proof also relies on the assumption that every real number can be represented by a (potentially infinite) decimal, which might or might not be accepted by someone asking the original question.
– bryn
Jul 22 '10 at 2:21
5
@bryn, this proof relies on a further assumption that the OP had specifically real numbers in mind when he asked the question.
– Mikhail Katz
Nov 25 '13 at 17:12
24
@BogdanAlexandru $frac{x+y}{2}$ is a number between $x$ and $y$
– Holographer
Sep 1 '14 at 15:39
3
$negneg Pimplies P$, yikes.
– Nikolaj-K
Nov 27 '15 at 3:06
3
@cat: Not completely sure what you mean, but see Double negative elimination and Constructive logic.
– Nikolaj-K
May 30 '16 at 21:31
|
show 3 more comments
56
This proof also relies on the assumption that every real number can be represented by a (potentially infinite) decimal, which might or might not be accepted by someone asking the original question.
– bryn
Jul 22 '10 at 2:21
5
@bryn, this proof relies on a further assumption that the OP had specifically real numbers in mind when he asked the question.
– Mikhail Katz
Nov 25 '13 at 17:12
24
@BogdanAlexandru $frac{x+y}{2}$ is a number between $x$ and $y$
– Holographer
Sep 1 '14 at 15:39
3
$negneg Pimplies P$, yikes.
– Nikolaj-K
Nov 27 '15 at 3:06
3
@cat: Not completely sure what you mean, but see Double negative elimination and Constructive logic.
– Nikolaj-K
May 30 '16 at 21:31
56
56
This proof also relies on the assumption that every real number can be represented by a (potentially infinite) decimal, which might or might not be accepted by someone asking the original question.
– bryn
Jul 22 '10 at 2:21
This proof also relies on the assumption that every real number can be represented by a (potentially infinite) decimal, which might or might not be accepted by someone asking the original question.
– bryn
Jul 22 '10 at 2:21
5
5
@bryn, this proof relies on a further assumption that the OP had specifically real numbers in mind when he asked the question.
– Mikhail Katz
Nov 25 '13 at 17:12
@bryn, this proof relies on a further assumption that the OP had specifically real numbers in mind when he asked the question.
– Mikhail Katz
Nov 25 '13 at 17:12
24
24
@BogdanAlexandru $frac{x+y}{2}$ is a number between $x$ and $y$
– Holographer
Sep 1 '14 at 15:39
@BogdanAlexandru $frac{x+y}{2}$ is a number between $x$ and $y$
– Holographer
Sep 1 '14 at 15:39
3
3
$negneg Pimplies P$, yikes.
– Nikolaj-K
Nov 27 '15 at 3:06
$negneg Pimplies P$, yikes.
– Nikolaj-K
Nov 27 '15 at 3:06
3
3
@cat: Not completely sure what you mean, but see Double negative elimination and Constructive logic.
– Nikolaj-K
May 30 '16 at 21:31
@cat: Not completely sure what you mean, but see Double negative elimination and Constructive logic.
– Nikolaj-K
May 30 '16 at 21:31
|
show 3 more comments
up vote
163
down vote
What I really don't like about all the above answers, is the underlying assumption that $1/3=0.3333ldots$ How do you know that? It seems to me like assuming the something which is already known.
A proof I really like is:
$$begin{align}
0.9999ldots × 10 &= 9.9999ldots\
0.9999ldots × (9+1) &= 9.9999ldots\
text{by distribution rule: }Space{15ex}{0ex}{0ex} \
0.9999ldots × 9 + 0.9999ldots × 1 &= 9.9999ldots\
0.9999ldots × 9 &= 9.9999dots-0.9999ldots\
0.9999ldots × 9 &= 9\
0.9999ldots &= 1
end{align}$$
The only things I need to assume is, that $9.999ldots - 0.999ldots = 9$ and that $0.999ldots × 10 = 9.999ldots$ These seems to me intuitive enough to take for granted.
The proof is from an old high school level math book of the Open University in Israel.
10
0.9999... x 9 = 8.999999...
– Sklivvz
May 3 '11 at 20:51
4
@Sklivvz, true, since 8.999....=9. Did you have trouble understanding the algebra I did?
– Elazar Leibovich
May 4 '11 at 5:55
11
Sklivvz, but my answer does not rely on the fact that 8.999...=9, did it? Or am I missing something (tried to make it a bit more clear)
– Elazar Leibovich
May 4 '11 at 5:59
8
@Michael I never evaluate9*0.9999
at step 3 or at any step. I leave the expression as it is, and then use the fact that if9x=9
thenx=1
in the last step.
– Elazar Leibovich
Feb 17 '14 at 9:00
2
BTW, the first sentence referring to "all the above answers" does not apply (and has not applied for most of the time this answer has been up), because (in the default view at least) none of them assume that $1/3 = 0.333dots$.
– ShreevatsaR
Jul 20 '14 at 17:41
|
show 17 more comments
up vote
163
down vote
What I really don't like about all the above answers, is the underlying assumption that $1/3=0.3333ldots$ How do you know that? It seems to me like assuming the something which is already known.
A proof I really like is:
$$begin{align}
0.9999ldots × 10 &= 9.9999ldots\
0.9999ldots × (9+1) &= 9.9999ldots\
text{by distribution rule: }Space{15ex}{0ex}{0ex} \
0.9999ldots × 9 + 0.9999ldots × 1 &= 9.9999ldots\
0.9999ldots × 9 &= 9.9999dots-0.9999ldots\
0.9999ldots × 9 &= 9\
0.9999ldots &= 1
end{align}$$
The only things I need to assume is, that $9.999ldots - 0.999ldots = 9$ and that $0.999ldots × 10 = 9.999ldots$ These seems to me intuitive enough to take for granted.
The proof is from an old high school level math book of the Open University in Israel.
10
0.9999... x 9 = 8.999999...
– Sklivvz
May 3 '11 at 20:51
4
@Sklivvz, true, since 8.999....=9. Did you have trouble understanding the algebra I did?
– Elazar Leibovich
May 4 '11 at 5:55
11
Sklivvz, but my answer does not rely on the fact that 8.999...=9, did it? Or am I missing something (tried to make it a bit more clear)
– Elazar Leibovich
May 4 '11 at 5:59
8
@Michael I never evaluate9*0.9999
at step 3 or at any step. I leave the expression as it is, and then use the fact that if9x=9
thenx=1
in the last step.
– Elazar Leibovich
Feb 17 '14 at 9:00
2
BTW, the first sentence referring to "all the above answers" does not apply (and has not applied for most of the time this answer has been up), because (in the default view at least) none of them assume that $1/3 = 0.333dots$.
– ShreevatsaR
Jul 20 '14 at 17:41
|
show 17 more comments
up vote
163
down vote
up vote
163
down vote
What I really don't like about all the above answers, is the underlying assumption that $1/3=0.3333ldots$ How do you know that? It seems to me like assuming the something which is already known.
A proof I really like is:
$$begin{align}
0.9999ldots × 10 &= 9.9999ldots\
0.9999ldots × (9+1) &= 9.9999ldots\
text{by distribution rule: }Space{15ex}{0ex}{0ex} \
0.9999ldots × 9 + 0.9999ldots × 1 &= 9.9999ldots\
0.9999ldots × 9 &= 9.9999dots-0.9999ldots\
0.9999ldots × 9 &= 9\
0.9999ldots &= 1
end{align}$$
The only things I need to assume is, that $9.999ldots - 0.999ldots = 9$ and that $0.999ldots × 10 = 9.999ldots$ These seems to me intuitive enough to take for granted.
The proof is from an old high school level math book of the Open University in Israel.
What I really don't like about all the above answers, is the underlying assumption that $1/3=0.3333ldots$ How do you know that? It seems to me like assuming the something which is already known.
A proof I really like is:
$$begin{align}
0.9999ldots × 10 &= 9.9999ldots\
0.9999ldots × (9+1) &= 9.9999ldots\
text{by distribution rule: }Space{15ex}{0ex}{0ex} \
0.9999ldots × 9 + 0.9999ldots × 1 &= 9.9999ldots\
0.9999ldots × 9 &= 9.9999dots-0.9999ldots\
0.9999ldots × 9 &= 9\
0.9999ldots &= 1
end{align}$$
The only things I need to assume is, that $9.999ldots - 0.999ldots = 9$ and that $0.999ldots × 10 = 9.999ldots$ These seems to me intuitive enough to take for granted.
The proof is from an old high school level math book of the Open University in Israel.
edited Oct 18 '14 at 13:45
community wiki
5 revs, 3 users 72%
Elazar Leibovich
10
0.9999... x 9 = 8.999999...
– Sklivvz
May 3 '11 at 20:51
4
@Sklivvz, true, since 8.999....=9. Did you have trouble understanding the algebra I did?
– Elazar Leibovich
May 4 '11 at 5:55
11
Sklivvz, but my answer does not rely on the fact that 8.999...=9, did it? Or am I missing something (tried to make it a bit more clear)
– Elazar Leibovich
May 4 '11 at 5:59
8
@Michael I never evaluate9*0.9999
at step 3 or at any step. I leave the expression as it is, and then use the fact that if9x=9
thenx=1
in the last step.
– Elazar Leibovich
Feb 17 '14 at 9:00
2
BTW, the first sentence referring to "all the above answers" does not apply (and has not applied for most of the time this answer has been up), because (in the default view at least) none of them assume that $1/3 = 0.333dots$.
– ShreevatsaR
Jul 20 '14 at 17:41
|
show 17 more comments
10
0.9999... x 9 = 8.999999...
– Sklivvz
May 3 '11 at 20:51
4
@Sklivvz, true, since 8.999....=9. Did you have trouble understanding the algebra I did?
– Elazar Leibovich
May 4 '11 at 5:55
11
Sklivvz, but my answer does not rely on the fact that 8.999...=9, did it? Or am I missing something (tried to make it a bit more clear)
– Elazar Leibovich
May 4 '11 at 5:59
8
@Michael I never evaluate9*0.9999
at step 3 or at any step. I leave the expression as it is, and then use the fact that if9x=9
thenx=1
in the last step.
– Elazar Leibovich
Feb 17 '14 at 9:00
2
BTW, the first sentence referring to "all the above answers" does not apply (and has not applied for most of the time this answer has been up), because (in the default view at least) none of them assume that $1/3 = 0.333dots$.
– ShreevatsaR
Jul 20 '14 at 17:41
10
10
0.9999... x 9 = 8.999999...
– Sklivvz
May 3 '11 at 20:51
0.9999... x 9 = 8.999999...
– Sklivvz
May 3 '11 at 20:51
4
4
@Sklivvz, true, since 8.999....=9. Did you have trouble understanding the algebra I did?
– Elazar Leibovich
May 4 '11 at 5:55
@Sklivvz, true, since 8.999....=9. Did you have trouble understanding the algebra I did?
– Elazar Leibovich
May 4 '11 at 5:55
11
11
Sklivvz, but my answer does not rely on the fact that 8.999...=9, did it? Or am I missing something (tried to make it a bit more clear)
– Elazar Leibovich
May 4 '11 at 5:59
Sklivvz, but my answer does not rely on the fact that 8.999...=9, did it? Or am I missing something (tried to make it a bit more clear)
– Elazar Leibovich
May 4 '11 at 5:59
8
8
@Michael I never evaluate
9*0.9999
at step 3 or at any step. I leave the expression as it is, and then use the fact that if 9x=9
then x=1
in the last step.– Elazar Leibovich
Feb 17 '14 at 9:00
@Michael I never evaluate
9*0.9999
at step 3 or at any step. I leave the expression as it is, and then use the fact that if 9x=9
then x=1
in the last step.– Elazar Leibovich
Feb 17 '14 at 9:00
2
2
BTW, the first sentence referring to "all the above answers" does not apply (and has not applied for most of the time this answer has been up), because (in the default view at least) none of them assume that $1/3 = 0.333dots$.
– ShreevatsaR
Jul 20 '14 at 17:41
BTW, the first sentence referring to "all the above answers" does not apply (and has not applied for most of the time this answer has been up), because (in the default view at least) none of them assume that $1/3 = 0.333dots$.
– ShreevatsaR
Jul 20 '14 at 17:41
|
show 17 more comments
up vote
149
down vote
Assuming:
- infinite decimals are series where the terms are the digits divided by the proper power of the base
- the infinite geometric series $a + a cdot r + a cdot r^2 + a cdot r^3 + cdots$ has sum $dfrac{a}{1 - r}$ as long as $|r|<1$
$$0.99999ldots = frac{9}{10} + frac{9}{10^2} + frac{9}{10^3} + cdots$$
This is the infinite geometric series with first term $a = frac{9}{10}$ and common ratio $r = frac{1}{10}$, so it has sum $$frac{frac{9}{10}}{1 - frac{1}{10}} = frac{frac{9}{10}}{frac{9}{10}} = 1.$$
9
Your method is a simple way of converting the decimal representation of a rational number into a fraction, e.g. $0.150150150...=sum_{ngeq 1}frac{150}{10^{3n}}=frac{0.150}{1-10^{-3}}=frac{50}{333}$
– Américo Tavares
Aug 16 '10 at 22:02
The question is where are you getting this common ratio of 1/10 and what law permits you to use it in this case?
– Serj Sagan
Aug 2 '16 at 19:11
@SerjSagan Generally, when not otherwise indicated, numbers are written in base 10. That makes the ratio of the values of successive "places" 10 or $frac{1}{10}$, depending on direction. This is the "... proper power of the base" piece of my point 1.
– Isaac
Aug 2 '16 at 19:17
add a comment |
up vote
149
down vote
Assuming:
- infinite decimals are series where the terms are the digits divided by the proper power of the base
- the infinite geometric series $a + a cdot r + a cdot r^2 + a cdot r^3 + cdots$ has sum $dfrac{a}{1 - r}$ as long as $|r|<1$
$$0.99999ldots = frac{9}{10} + frac{9}{10^2} + frac{9}{10^3} + cdots$$
This is the infinite geometric series with first term $a = frac{9}{10}$ and common ratio $r = frac{1}{10}$, so it has sum $$frac{frac{9}{10}}{1 - frac{1}{10}} = frac{frac{9}{10}}{frac{9}{10}} = 1.$$
9
Your method is a simple way of converting the decimal representation of a rational number into a fraction, e.g. $0.150150150...=sum_{ngeq 1}frac{150}{10^{3n}}=frac{0.150}{1-10^{-3}}=frac{50}{333}$
– Américo Tavares
Aug 16 '10 at 22:02
The question is where are you getting this common ratio of 1/10 and what law permits you to use it in this case?
– Serj Sagan
Aug 2 '16 at 19:11
@SerjSagan Generally, when not otherwise indicated, numbers are written in base 10. That makes the ratio of the values of successive "places" 10 or $frac{1}{10}$, depending on direction. This is the "... proper power of the base" piece of my point 1.
– Isaac
Aug 2 '16 at 19:17
add a comment |
up vote
149
down vote
up vote
149
down vote
Assuming:
- infinite decimals are series where the terms are the digits divided by the proper power of the base
- the infinite geometric series $a + a cdot r + a cdot r^2 + a cdot r^3 + cdots$ has sum $dfrac{a}{1 - r}$ as long as $|r|<1$
$$0.99999ldots = frac{9}{10} + frac{9}{10^2} + frac{9}{10^3} + cdots$$
This is the infinite geometric series with first term $a = frac{9}{10}$ and common ratio $r = frac{1}{10}$, so it has sum $$frac{frac{9}{10}}{1 - frac{1}{10}} = frac{frac{9}{10}}{frac{9}{10}} = 1.$$
Assuming:
- infinite decimals are series where the terms are the digits divided by the proper power of the base
- the infinite geometric series $a + a cdot r + a cdot r^2 + a cdot r^3 + cdots$ has sum $dfrac{a}{1 - r}$ as long as $|r|<1$
$$0.99999ldots = frac{9}{10} + frac{9}{10^2} + frac{9}{10^3} + cdots$$
This is the infinite geometric series with first term $a = frac{9}{10}$ and common ratio $r = frac{1}{10}$, so it has sum $$frac{frac{9}{10}}{1 - frac{1}{10}} = frac{frac{9}{10}}{frac{9}{10}} = 1.$$
edited Nov 16 '13 at 16:42
community wiki
2 revs
Isaac
9
Your method is a simple way of converting the decimal representation of a rational number into a fraction, e.g. $0.150150150...=sum_{ngeq 1}frac{150}{10^{3n}}=frac{0.150}{1-10^{-3}}=frac{50}{333}$
– Américo Tavares
Aug 16 '10 at 22:02
The question is where are you getting this common ratio of 1/10 and what law permits you to use it in this case?
– Serj Sagan
Aug 2 '16 at 19:11
@SerjSagan Generally, when not otherwise indicated, numbers are written in base 10. That makes the ratio of the values of successive "places" 10 or $frac{1}{10}$, depending on direction. This is the "... proper power of the base" piece of my point 1.
– Isaac
Aug 2 '16 at 19:17
add a comment |
9
Your method is a simple way of converting the decimal representation of a rational number into a fraction, e.g. $0.150150150...=sum_{ngeq 1}frac{150}{10^{3n}}=frac{0.150}{1-10^{-3}}=frac{50}{333}$
– Américo Tavares
Aug 16 '10 at 22:02
The question is where are you getting this common ratio of 1/10 and what law permits you to use it in this case?
– Serj Sagan
Aug 2 '16 at 19:11
@SerjSagan Generally, when not otherwise indicated, numbers are written in base 10. That makes the ratio of the values of successive "places" 10 or $frac{1}{10}$, depending on direction. This is the "... proper power of the base" piece of my point 1.
– Isaac
Aug 2 '16 at 19:17
9
9
Your method is a simple way of converting the decimal representation of a rational number into a fraction, e.g. $0.150150150...=sum_{ngeq 1}frac{150}{10^{3n}}=frac{0.150}{1-10^{-3}}=frac{50}{333}$
– Américo Tavares
Aug 16 '10 at 22:02
Your method is a simple way of converting the decimal representation of a rational number into a fraction, e.g. $0.150150150...=sum_{ngeq 1}frac{150}{10^{3n}}=frac{0.150}{1-10^{-3}}=frac{50}{333}$
– Américo Tavares
Aug 16 '10 at 22:02
The question is where are you getting this common ratio of 1/10 and what law permits you to use it in this case?
– Serj Sagan
Aug 2 '16 at 19:11
The question is where are you getting this common ratio of 1/10 and what law permits you to use it in this case?
– Serj Sagan
Aug 2 '16 at 19:11
@SerjSagan Generally, when not otherwise indicated, numbers are written in base 10. That makes the ratio of the values of successive "places" 10 or $frac{1}{10}$, depending on direction. This is the "... proper power of the base" piece of my point 1.
– Isaac
Aug 2 '16 at 19:17
@SerjSagan Generally, when not otherwise indicated, numbers are written in base 10. That makes the ratio of the values of successive "places" 10 or $frac{1}{10}$, depending on direction. This is the "... proper power of the base" piece of my point 1.
– Isaac
Aug 2 '16 at 19:17
add a comment |
up vote
68
down vote
$$x=0.999...$$
$$10x=9.999...$$
$$10x-x=9.999...-0.999...$$
$$9x=9$$
$$x=1$$
thus, $0.999...=1$
1
This is the most intuitive argument, although some might say "But 10x-x isn't 9, because there's going to be a mismatch all the way to the right" - Noah's more complex deals with that.
– Charles Stewart
Jul 21 '10 at 10:55
10x - x != 9. 10x - x would be 8.9999...1. However infinite the extent of 9s is in x, if we multiply it by 10, the nines are shifted left by one position and a zero inserted at the "last" place, and then when you subtract the other number there is a nine subtracted from a zero at the far right. Otherwise we'd have to give 0.999.. some unusual properties like automatically increasing the number of nines when it is multiplied. It would not be just an ordinary number. Maybe that's the problem. 0.999... might just not be an ordinary type number as some people are using it.
– Doug Treadwell
Jul 23 '10 at 2:19
8
@Doug It's incorrect to talk about the "number of nines" because infinity minus a number = infinity. Infinity is transcendent. It means "uncountable". If you take infinity and slide it left a little bit, it's still infinity long.
– ErikE
Sep 25 '10 at 7:00
The problem is the assumption that9x = 9
when in fact9x = 8.999...
your proof is flawed.
– Serj Sagan
Aug 2 '16 at 19:16
9
@SerjSagan that line isn't an assumption, it's a deduction. If you believe that $9.999dots - 0.999dots = 9$, then you must therefore believe that $9x = 9$.
– Omnomnomnom
Dec 15 '16 at 17:03
|
show 1 more comment
up vote
68
down vote
$$x=0.999...$$
$$10x=9.999...$$
$$10x-x=9.999...-0.999...$$
$$9x=9$$
$$x=1$$
thus, $0.999...=1$
1
This is the most intuitive argument, although some might say "But 10x-x isn't 9, because there's going to be a mismatch all the way to the right" - Noah's more complex deals with that.
– Charles Stewart
Jul 21 '10 at 10:55
10x - x != 9. 10x - x would be 8.9999...1. However infinite the extent of 9s is in x, if we multiply it by 10, the nines are shifted left by one position and a zero inserted at the "last" place, and then when you subtract the other number there is a nine subtracted from a zero at the far right. Otherwise we'd have to give 0.999.. some unusual properties like automatically increasing the number of nines when it is multiplied. It would not be just an ordinary number. Maybe that's the problem. 0.999... might just not be an ordinary type number as some people are using it.
– Doug Treadwell
Jul 23 '10 at 2:19
8
@Doug It's incorrect to talk about the "number of nines" because infinity minus a number = infinity. Infinity is transcendent. It means "uncountable". If you take infinity and slide it left a little bit, it's still infinity long.
– ErikE
Sep 25 '10 at 7:00
The problem is the assumption that9x = 9
when in fact9x = 8.999...
your proof is flawed.
– Serj Sagan
Aug 2 '16 at 19:16
9
@SerjSagan that line isn't an assumption, it's a deduction. If you believe that $9.999dots - 0.999dots = 9$, then you must therefore believe that $9x = 9$.
– Omnomnomnom
Dec 15 '16 at 17:03
|
show 1 more comment
up vote
68
down vote
up vote
68
down vote
$$x=0.999...$$
$$10x=9.999...$$
$$10x-x=9.999...-0.999...$$
$$9x=9$$
$$x=1$$
thus, $0.999...=1$
$$x=0.999...$$
$$10x=9.999...$$
$$10x-x=9.999...-0.999...$$
$$9x=9$$
$$x=1$$
thus, $0.999...=1$
edited Dec 18 '16 at 16:54
community wiki
2 revs, 2 users 53%
Pieces
1
This is the most intuitive argument, although some might say "But 10x-x isn't 9, because there's going to be a mismatch all the way to the right" - Noah's more complex deals with that.
– Charles Stewart
Jul 21 '10 at 10:55
10x - x != 9. 10x - x would be 8.9999...1. However infinite the extent of 9s is in x, if we multiply it by 10, the nines are shifted left by one position and a zero inserted at the "last" place, and then when you subtract the other number there is a nine subtracted from a zero at the far right. Otherwise we'd have to give 0.999.. some unusual properties like automatically increasing the number of nines when it is multiplied. It would not be just an ordinary number. Maybe that's the problem. 0.999... might just not be an ordinary type number as some people are using it.
– Doug Treadwell
Jul 23 '10 at 2:19
8
@Doug It's incorrect to talk about the "number of nines" because infinity minus a number = infinity. Infinity is transcendent. It means "uncountable". If you take infinity and slide it left a little bit, it's still infinity long.
– ErikE
Sep 25 '10 at 7:00
The problem is the assumption that9x = 9
when in fact9x = 8.999...
your proof is flawed.
– Serj Sagan
Aug 2 '16 at 19:16
9
@SerjSagan that line isn't an assumption, it's a deduction. If you believe that $9.999dots - 0.999dots = 9$, then you must therefore believe that $9x = 9$.
– Omnomnomnom
Dec 15 '16 at 17:03
|
show 1 more comment
1
This is the most intuitive argument, although some might say "But 10x-x isn't 9, because there's going to be a mismatch all the way to the right" - Noah's more complex deals with that.
– Charles Stewart
Jul 21 '10 at 10:55
10x - x != 9. 10x - x would be 8.9999...1. However infinite the extent of 9s is in x, if we multiply it by 10, the nines are shifted left by one position and a zero inserted at the "last" place, and then when you subtract the other number there is a nine subtracted from a zero at the far right. Otherwise we'd have to give 0.999.. some unusual properties like automatically increasing the number of nines when it is multiplied. It would not be just an ordinary number. Maybe that's the problem. 0.999... might just not be an ordinary type number as some people are using it.
– Doug Treadwell
Jul 23 '10 at 2:19
8
@Doug It's incorrect to talk about the "number of nines" because infinity minus a number = infinity. Infinity is transcendent. It means "uncountable". If you take infinity and slide it left a little bit, it's still infinity long.
– ErikE
Sep 25 '10 at 7:00
The problem is the assumption that9x = 9
when in fact9x = 8.999...
your proof is flawed.
– Serj Sagan
Aug 2 '16 at 19:16
9
@SerjSagan that line isn't an assumption, it's a deduction. If you believe that $9.999dots - 0.999dots = 9$, then you must therefore believe that $9x = 9$.
– Omnomnomnom
Dec 15 '16 at 17:03
1
1
This is the most intuitive argument, although some might say "But 10x-x isn't 9, because there's going to be a mismatch all the way to the right" - Noah's more complex deals with that.
– Charles Stewart
Jul 21 '10 at 10:55
This is the most intuitive argument, although some might say "But 10x-x isn't 9, because there's going to be a mismatch all the way to the right" - Noah's more complex deals with that.
– Charles Stewart
Jul 21 '10 at 10:55
10x - x != 9. 10x - x would be 8.9999...1. However infinite the extent of 9s is in x, if we multiply it by 10, the nines are shifted left by one position and a zero inserted at the "last" place, and then when you subtract the other number there is a nine subtracted from a zero at the far right. Otherwise we'd have to give 0.999.. some unusual properties like automatically increasing the number of nines when it is multiplied. It would not be just an ordinary number. Maybe that's the problem. 0.999... might just not be an ordinary type number as some people are using it.
– Doug Treadwell
Jul 23 '10 at 2:19
10x - x != 9. 10x - x would be 8.9999...1. However infinite the extent of 9s is in x, if we multiply it by 10, the nines are shifted left by one position and a zero inserted at the "last" place, and then when you subtract the other number there is a nine subtracted from a zero at the far right. Otherwise we'd have to give 0.999.. some unusual properties like automatically increasing the number of nines when it is multiplied. It would not be just an ordinary number. Maybe that's the problem. 0.999... might just not be an ordinary type number as some people are using it.
– Doug Treadwell
Jul 23 '10 at 2:19
8
8
@Doug It's incorrect to talk about the "number of nines" because infinity minus a number = infinity. Infinity is transcendent. It means "uncountable". If you take infinity and slide it left a little bit, it's still infinity long.
– ErikE
Sep 25 '10 at 7:00
@Doug It's incorrect to talk about the "number of nines" because infinity minus a number = infinity. Infinity is transcendent. It means "uncountable". If you take infinity and slide it left a little bit, it's still infinity long.
– ErikE
Sep 25 '10 at 7:00
The problem is the assumption that
9x = 9
when in fact 9x = 8.999...
your proof is flawed.– Serj Sagan
Aug 2 '16 at 19:16
The problem is the assumption that
9x = 9
when in fact 9x = 8.999...
your proof is flawed.– Serj Sagan
Aug 2 '16 at 19:16
9
9
@SerjSagan that line isn't an assumption, it's a deduction. If you believe that $9.999dots - 0.999dots = 9$, then you must therefore believe that $9x = 9$.
– Omnomnomnom
Dec 15 '16 at 17:03
@SerjSagan that line isn't an assumption, it's a deduction. If you believe that $9.999dots - 0.999dots = 9$, then you must therefore believe that $9x = 9$.
– Omnomnomnom
Dec 15 '16 at 17:03
|
show 1 more comment
up vote
52
down vote
Okay I burned a lot of reputation points (at least for me) on MathOverflow to gain clarity on how to give some intuition into this problem, so hopefully this answer will be at least be somewhat illuminating.
To gain a deeper understanding of what is going on, first we need to answer the question, "What is a number?"
There are a lot of ways to define numbers, but in general numbers are thought of as symbols that represent sets.
This is easy for things like the natural numbers. So 10 would correspond to the set with ten things -- like a bag of ten stones. Pretty straight forward.
The tricky part is that when we consider ten a subset of the real numbers, we actually redefine it. This is not emphasized even in higher mathematics classes, like real analysis; it just happens when we define the real numbers.
So what is 10 when constructed in the real numbers? Well, at least with the Dedekind cut version of the real numbers, all real numbers correspond to a set with an infinite amount of elements. This makes 10 under the hood look drastically different, although in practice it operates exactly the same.
So let's return to the question: Why is 10 the same as 9.99999? Because the real numbers have this completely surprising quality, where there is no next real number. So when you have two real numbers that are as close together as possible, they are the same. I can't think of any physical object that has this quality, but it's how the real numbers work (makes "real" seem ironic).
With integers (bag of stones version) this is not the same. When you have two integers as close to each other as possible they are still different, and they are distance one apart.
Put another way, 10 bag of stones are not the same as 9.9999999 but 10 the natural number, where natural numbers are a subset of the real numbers is.
The bottom line is that the real numbers have these tricky edge cases that are hard to understand intuitively. Don't worry, your intuition is not really failing you. :)
I didn't feel confident answering until I got this Terence Tao link:
(Wayback Machine) https://web.archive.org/web/20100725014132/http://www.google.com:80/buzz/114134834346472219368/RarPutThCJv/In-the-foundations-of-mathematics-the-standard
(PDF, page 12) https://terrytao.files.wordpress.com/2011/06/blog-book.pdf
4
The link doesn't work.
– user 170039
Jan 5 '16 at 15:08
I'm not sure that most people think of real numbers as representing sets. Indeed, probably few of those who didn't study mathematics or attend mathematics lectures have even heard of the Dedekind construction. The common visualization of real numbers is as points on a line.
– celtschk
Aug 14 '16 at 9:03
2
the link is dead
– baxx
Sep 10 '16 at 20:43
As a smart person, I actually like this answer better than balpha and Elezar Laibovich's answer. It's good enough for me because I can figure out from it a fuller answer that explains how people were looking for a definition of a real number in ZF such that the set of all of them is a complete ordered field so they found one and proved it's a complete ordered field. math.stackexchange.com/questions/2437893/… actually says what a real natural number is. Those answers aren't bad either because I can prove that all real numbers have a decimal representation.
– Timothy
May 17 at 1:34
add a comment |
up vote
52
down vote
Okay I burned a lot of reputation points (at least for me) on MathOverflow to gain clarity on how to give some intuition into this problem, so hopefully this answer will be at least be somewhat illuminating.
To gain a deeper understanding of what is going on, first we need to answer the question, "What is a number?"
There are a lot of ways to define numbers, but in general numbers are thought of as symbols that represent sets.
This is easy for things like the natural numbers. So 10 would correspond to the set with ten things -- like a bag of ten stones. Pretty straight forward.
The tricky part is that when we consider ten a subset of the real numbers, we actually redefine it. This is not emphasized even in higher mathematics classes, like real analysis; it just happens when we define the real numbers.
So what is 10 when constructed in the real numbers? Well, at least with the Dedekind cut version of the real numbers, all real numbers correspond to a set with an infinite amount of elements. This makes 10 under the hood look drastically different, although in practice it operates exactly the same.
So let's return to the question: Why is 10 the same as 9.99999? Because the real numbers have this completely surprising quality, where there is no next real number. So when you have two real numbers that are as close together as possible, they are the same. I can't think of any physical object that has this quality, but it's how the real numbers work (makes "real" seem ironic).
With integers (bag of stones version) this is not the same. When you have two integers as close to each other as possible they are still different, and they are distance one apart.
Put another way, 10 bag of stones are not the same as 9.9999999 but 10 the natural number, where natural numbers are a subset of the real numbers is.
The bottom line is that the real numbers have these tricky edge cases that are hard to understand intuitively. Don't worry, your intuition is not really failing you. :)
I didn't feel confident answering until I got this Terence Tao link:
(Wayback Machine) https://web.archive.org/web/20100725014132/http://www.google.com:80/buzz/114134834346472219368/RarPutThCJv/In-the-foundations-of-mathematics-the-standard
(PDF, page 12) https://terrytao.files.wordpress.com/2011/06/blog-book.pdf
4
The link doesn't work.
– user 170039
Jan 5 '16 at 15:08
I'm not sure that most people think of real numbers as representing sets. Indeed, probably few of those who didn't study mathematics or attend mathematics lectures have even heard of the Dedekind construction. The common visualization of real numbers is as points on a line.
– celtschk
Aug 14 '16 at 9:03
2
the link is dead
– baxx
Sep 10 '16 at 20:43
As a smart person, I actually like this answer better than balpha and Elezar Laibovich's answer. It's good enough for me because I can figure out from it a fuller answer that explains how people were looking for a definition of a real number in ZF such that the set of all of them is a complete ordered field so they found one and proved it's a complete ordered field. math.stackexchange.com/questions/2437893/… actually says what a real natural number is. Those answers aren't bad either because I can prove that all real numbers have a decimal representation.
– Timothy
May 17 at 1:34
add a comment |
up vote
52
down vote
up vote
52
down vote
Okay I burned a lot of reputation points (at least for me) on MathOverflow to gain clarity on how to give some intuition into this problem, so hopefully this answer will be at least be somewhat illuminating.
To gain a deeper understanding of what is going on, first we need to answer the question, "What is a number?"
There are a lot of ways to define numbers, but in general numbers are thought of as symbols that represent sets.
This is easy for things like the natural numbers. So 10 would correspond to the set with ten things -- like a bag of ten stones. Pretty straight forward.
The tricky part is that when we consider ten a subset of the real numbers, we actually redefine it. This is not emphasized even in higher mathematics classes, like real analysis; it just happens when we define the real numbers.
So what is 10 when constructed in the real numbers? Well, at least with the Dedekind cut version of the real numbers, all real numbers correspond to a set with an infinite amount of elements. This makes 10 under the hood look drastically different, although in practice it operates exactly the same.
So let's return to the question: Why is 10 the same as 9.99999? Because the real numbers have this completely surprising quality, where there is no next real number. So when you have two real numbers that are as close together as possible, they are the same. I can't think of any physical object that has this quality, but it's how the real numbers work (makes "real" seem ironic).
With integers (bag of stones version) this is not the same. When you have two integers as close to each other as possible they are still different, and they are distance one apart.
Put another way, 10 bag of stones are not the same as 9.9999999 but 10 the natural number, where natural numbers are a subset of the real numbers is.
The bottom line is that the real numbers have these tricky edge cases that are hard to understand intuitively. Don't worry, your intuition is not really failing you. :)
I didn't feel confident answering until I got this Terence Tao link:
(Wayback Machine) https://web.archive.org/web/20100725014132/http://www.google.com:80/buzz/114134834346472219368/RarPutThCJv/In-the-foundations-of-mathematics-the-standard
(PDF, page 12) https://terrytao.files.wordpress.com/2011/06/blog-book.pdf
Okay I burned a lot of reputation points (at least for me) on MathOverflow to gain clarity on how to give some intuition into this problem, so hopefully this answer will be at least be somewhat illuminating.
To gain a deeper understanding of what is going on, first we need to answer the question, "What is a number?"
There are a lot of ways to define numbers, but in general numbers are thought of as symbols that represent sets.
This is easy for things like the natural numbers. So 10 would correspond to the set with ten things -- like a bag of ten stones. Pretty straight forward.
The tricky part is that when we consider ten a subset of the real numbers, we actually redefine it. This is not emphasized even in higher mathematics classes, like real analysis; it just happens when we define the real numbers.
So what is 10 when constructed in the real numbers? Well, at least with the Dedekind cut version of the real numbers, all real numbers correspond to a set with an infinite amount of elements. This makes 10 under the hood look drastically different, although in practice it operates exactly the same.
So let's return to the question: Why is 10 the same as 9.99999? Because the real numbers have this completely surprising quality, where there is no next real number. So when you have two real numbers that are as close together as possible, they are the same. I can't think of any physical object that has this quality, but it's how the real numbers work (makes "real" seem ironic).
With integers (bag of stones version) this is not the same. When you have two integers as close to each other as possible they are still different, and they are distance one apart.
Put another way, 10 bag of stones are not the same as 9.9999999 but 10 the natural number, where natural numbers are a subset of the real numbers is.
The bottom line is that the real numbers have these tricky edge cases that are hard to understand intuitively. Don't worry, your intuition is not really failing you. :)
I didn't feel confident answering until I got this Terence Tao link:
(Wayback Machine) https://web.archive.org/web/20100725014132/http://www.google.com:80/buzz/114134834346472219368/RarPutThCJv/In-the-foundations-of-mathematics-the-standard
(PDF, page 12) https://terrytao.files.wordpress.com/2011/06/blog-book.pdf
edited Dec 30 '17 at 20:20
community wiki
4 revs, 2 users 91%
Jonathan Fischoff
4
The link doesn't work.
– user 170039
Jan 5 '16 at 15:08
I'm not sure that most people think of real numbers as representing sets. Indeed, probably few of those who didn't study mathematics or attend mathematics lectures have even heard of the Dedekind construction. The common visualization of real numbers is as points on a line.
– celtschk
Aug 14 '16 at 9:03
2
the link is dead
– baxx
Sep 10 '16 at 20:43
As a smart person, I actually like this answer better than balpha and Elezar Laibovich's answer. It's good enough for me because I can figure out from it a fuller answer that explains how people were looking for a definition of a real number in ZF such that the set of all of them is a complete ordered field so they found one and proved it's a complete ordered field. math.stackexchange.com/questions/2437893/… actually says what a real natural number is. Those answers aren't bad either because I can prove that all real numbers have a decimal representation.
– Timothy
May 17 at 1:34
add a comment |
4
The link doesn't work.
– user 170039
Jan 5 '16 at 15:08
I'm not sure that most people think of real numbers as representing sets. Indeed, probably few of those who didn't study mathematics or attend mathematics lectures have even heard of the Dedekind construction. The common visualization of real numbers is as points on a line.
– celtschk
Aug 14 '16 at 9:03
2
the link is dead
– baxx
Sep 10 '16 at 20:43
As a smart person, I actually like this answer better than balpha and Elezar Laibovich's answer. It's good enough for me because I can figure out from it a fuller answer that explains how people were looking for a definition of a real number in ZF such that the set of all of them is a complete ordered field so they found one and proved it's a complete ordered field. math.stackexchange.com/questions/2437893/… actually says what a real natural number is. Those answers aren't bad either because I can prove that all real numbers have a decimal representation.
– Timothy
May 17 at 1:34
4
4
The link doesn't work.
– user 170039
Jan 5 '16 at 15:08
The link doesn't work.
– user 170039
Jan 5 '16 at 15:08
I'm not sure that most people think of real numbers as representing sets. Indeed, probably few of those who didn't study mathematics or attend mathematics lectures have even heard of the Dedekind construction. The common visualization of real numbers is as points on a line.
– celtschk
Aug 14 '16 at 9:03
I'm not sure that most people think of real numbers as representing sets. Indeed, probably few of those who didn't study mathematics or attend mathematics lectures have even heard of the Dedekind construction. The common visualization of real numbers is as points on a line.
– celtschk
Aug 14 '16 at 9:03
2
2
the link is dead
– baxx
Sep 10 '16 at 20:43
the link is dead
– baxx
Sep 10 '16 at 20:43
As a smart person, I actually like this answer better than balpha and Elezar Laibovich's answer. It's good enough for me because I can figure out from it a fuller answer that explains how people were looking for a definition of a real number in ZF such that the set of all of them is a complete ordered field so they found one and proved it's a complete ordered field. math.stackexchange.com/questions/2437893/… actually says what a real natural number is. Those answers aren't bad either because I can prove that all real numbers have a decimal representation.
– Timothy
May 17 at 1:34
As a smart person, I actually like this answer better than balpha and Elezar Laibovich's answer. It's good enough for me because I can figure out from it a fuller answer that explains how people were looking for a definition of a real number in ZF such that the set of all of them is a complete ordered field so they found one and proved it's a complete ordered field. math.stackexchange.com/questions/2437893/… actually says what a real natural number is. Those answers aren't bad either because I can prove that all real numbers have a decimal representation.
– Timothy
May 17 at 1:34
add a comment |
up vote
42
down vote
There are genuine conceptual difficulties implicit in this question. The transition from the rational numbers to the real numbers is a difficult one, and it took a long time and a lot of thought to make it truly rigorous. It has been pointed out in other answers that the notation $0.999999ldots$ is just a shorthand notation for the infinite geometric series $sumlimits_{n=1}^{infty} 9left( frac{1}{10} right)^{n},$ which has sum $1.$ This is factually correct, but still sweeps some of the conceptual questions under the carpet. There are questions to be addressed about what we mean when we write down (or pretend to) an infinite decimal, or an infinite series. Either of those devices is just a shorthand notation which mathematicians agree will represent some numbers, given a set of ground rules. Let me try to present an argument to suggest that if the notation $0.99999ldots$ is to meaningfully represent any real number, then that number could be nothing other than the real number $1$, if we can agree that some truths are "self-evident".
Surely we can agree that the real number it represents can't be strictly greater than $1$, if it does indeed represent a real number. Let's now convince ourselves that it can't be a real number strictly less than $1,$
if it makes any sense at all. Well, if it was a real number $r < 1,$ that real number would be greater than or equal to $sumlimits_{n=1}^{k} 9left( frac{1}{10} right)^{n}$ for any finite integer $k.$ This last number is the decimal $0.99 ldots 9 $ which terminates after $k$ occurrences of $9,$ and differs from $1$ by $frac{1}{10^{k}}.$ Since $0 < r <1,$ there is a value of $k$ such that $frac{1}{10^{k}} < 1-r,$ so $1 - frac{1}{10^{k}} >r.$ Hence $sumlimits_{n=1}^{k} 9left( frac{1}{10} right)^{n} > r.$ But this can't be, because we agreed that $r$ should be greater than or equal to each of those truncated sums.
Have I proved that the recurring decimal is equal to $1$? Not really- what I have proved is that if we allow that recurring decimal to meaningfully represent any real number, that real number has to be $1,$ since it can't be strictly less than $1$ and can't be strictly greater than $1$. At this point, it becomes a matter of convention to agree that the real number $1$ can be represented in that form, and that convention will be consistent with our usual operations with real numbers and ordering of the real numbers, and equating the expression with any other real number would not maintain that consistency.
5
This is the best answer here; it's a shame it was posted four years later so it's gotten so little attention.
– Eric Wofsey
Oct 4 '15 at 0:44
1
If I am not mistaken then this answer also answers the question of this post.
– user 170039
Jan 6 '16 at 14:32
By the way, I was thinking that maybe you could write an answer for the linked post as well (or else, can you just tell me how can I give a link to this answer in a comment below my post?).
– user 170039
Jan 6 '16 at 14:40
1
I'm not sure how to set up links on here ( maybe the "cite") button. I am basically agreeing with what you say in your post.
– Geoff Robinson
Jan 6 '16 at 15:03
I think that the "evident" issue of a number being an abstract concept existing in isolation from any positional representation should also be explicitly stated. One then proceeds to give rules as to how the positional representation works (as you did), and from these rules it follows that all real numbers have an infinitely long representation in any base, and rational numbers have a finitely long representation in some bases. The integers are a special case of rational numbers that have a finite representation in all bases.
– Kuba Ober
Jul 28 '16 at 19:55
add a comment |
up vote
42
down vote
There are genuine conceptual difficulties implicit in this question. The transition from the rational numbers to the real numbers is a difficult one, and it took a long time and a lot of thought to make it truly rigorous. It has been pointed out in other answers that the notation $0.999999ldots$ is just a shorthand notation for the infinite geometric series $sumlimits_{n=1}^{infty} 9left( frac{1}{10} right)^{n},$ which has sum $1.$ This is factually correct, but still sweeps some of the conceptual questions under the carpet. There are questions to be addressed about what we mean when we write down (or pretend to) an infinite decimal, or an infinite series. Either of those devices is just a shorthand notation which mathematicians agree will represent some numbers, given a set of ground rules. Let me try to present an argument to suggest that if the notation $0.99999ldots$ is to meaningfully represent any real number, then that number could be nothing other than the real number $1$, if we can agree that some truths are "self-evident".
Surely we can agree that the real number it represents can't be strictly greater than $1$, if it does indeed represent a real number. Let's now convince ourselves that it can't be a real number strictly less than $1,$
if it makes any sense at all. Well, if it was a real number $r < 1,$ that real number would be greater than or equal to $sumlimits_{n=1}^{k} 9left( frac{1}{10} right)^{n}$ for any finite integer $k.$ This last number is the decimal $0.99 ldots 9 $ which terminates after $k$ occurrences of $9,$ and differs from $1$ by $frac{1}{10^{k}}.$ Since $0 < r <1,$ there is a value of $k$ such that $frac{1}{10^{k}} < 1-r,$ so $1 - frac{1}{10^{k}} >r.$ Hence $sumlimits_{n=1}^{k} 9left( frac{1}{10} right)^{n} > r.$ But this can't be, because we agreed that $r$ should be greater than or equal to each of those truncated sums.
Have I proved that the recurring decimal is equal to $1$? Not really- what I have proved is that if we allow that recurring decimal to meaningfully represent any real number, that real number has to be $1,$ since it can't be strictly less than $1$ and can't be strictly greater than $1$. At this point, it becomes a matter of convention to agree that the real number $1$ can be represented in that form, and that convention will be consistent with our usual operations with real numbers and ordering of the real numbers, and equating the expression with any other real number would not maintain that consistency.
5
This is the best answer here; it's a shame it was posted four years later so it's gotten so little attention.
– Eric Wofsey
Oct 4 '15 at 0:44
1
If I am not mistaken then this answer also answers the question of this post.
– user 170039
Jan 6 '16 at 14:32
By the way, I was thinking that maybe you could write an answer for the linked post as well (or else, can you just tell me how can I give a link to this answer in a comment below my post?).
– user 170039
Jan 6 '16 at 14:40
1
I'm not sure how to set up links on here ( maybe the "cite") button. I am basically agreeing with what you say in your post.
– Geoff Robinson
Jan 6 '16 at 15:03
I think that the "evident" issue of a number being an abstract concept existing in isolation from any positional representation should also be explicitly stated. One then proceeds to give rules as to how the positional representation works (as you did), and from these rules it follows that all real numbers have an infinitely long representation in any base, and rational numbers have a finitely long representation in some bases. The integers are a special case of rational numbers that have a finite representation in all bases.
– Kuba Ober
Jul 28 '16 at 19:55
add a comment |
up vote
42
down vote
up vote
42
down vote
There are genuine conceptual difficulties implicit in this question. The transition from the rational numbers to the real numbers is a difficult one, and it took a long time and a lot of thought to make it truly rigorous. It has been pointed out in other answers that the notation $0.999999ldots$ is just a shorthand notation for the infinite geometric series $sumlimits_{n=1}^{infty} 9left( frac{1}{10} right)^{n},$ which has sum $1.$ This is factually correct, but still sweeps some of the conceptual questions under the carpet. There are questions to be addressed about what we mean when we write down (or pretend to) an infinite decimal, or an infinite series. Either of those devices is just a shorthand notation which mathematicians agree will represent some numbers, given a set of ground rules. Let me try to present an argument to suggest that if the notation $0.99999ldots$ is to meaningfully represent any real number, then that number could be nothing other than the real number $1$, if we can agree that some truths are "self-evident".
Surely we can agree that the real number it represents can't be strictly greater than $1$, if it does indeed represent a real number. Let's now convince ourselves that it can't be a real number strictly less than $1,$
if it makes any sense at all. Well, if it was a real number $r < 1,$ that real number would be greater than or equal to $sumlimits_{n=1}^{k} 9left( frac{1}{10} right)^{n}$ for any finite integer $k.$ This last number is the decimal $0.99 ldots 9 $ which terminates after $k$ occurrences of $9,$ and differs from $1$ by $frac{1}{10^{k}}.$ Since $0 < r <1,$ there is a value of $k$ such that $frac{1}{10^{k}} < 1-r,$ so $1 - frac{1}{10^{k}} >r.$ Hence $sumlimits_{n=1}^{k} 9left( frac{1}{10} right)^{n} > r.$ But this can't be, because we agreed that $r$ should be greater than or equal to each of those truncated sums.
Have I proved that the recurring decimal is equal to $1$? Not really- what I have proved is that if we allow that recurring decimal to meaningfully represent any real number, that real number has to be $1,$ since it can't be strictly less than $1$ and can't be strictly greater than $1$. At this point, it becomes a matter of convention to agree that the real number $1$ can be represented in that form, and that convention will be consistent with our usual operations with real numbers and ordering of the real numbers, and equating the expression with any other real number would not maintain that consistency.
There are genuine conceptual difficulties implicit in this question. The transition from the rational numbers to the real numbers is a difficult one, and it took a long time and a lot of thought to make it truly rigorous. It has been pointed out in other answers that the notation $0.999999ldots$ is just a shorthand notation for the infinite geometric series $sumlimits_{n=1}^{infty} 9left( frac{1}{10} right)^{n},$ which has sum $1.$ This is factually correct, but still sweeps some of the conceptual questions under the carpet. There are questions to be addressed about what we mean when we write down (or pretend to) an infinite decimal, or an infinite series. Either of those devices is just a shorthand notation which mathematicians agree will represent some numbers, given a set of ground rules. Let me try to present an argument to suggest that if the notation $0.99999ldots$ is to meaningfully represent any real number, then that number could be nothing other than the real number $1$, if we can agree that some truths are "self-evident".
Surely we can agree that the real number it represents can't be strictly greater than $1$, if it does indeed represent a real number. Let's now convince ourselves that it can't be a real number strictly less than $1,$
if it makes any sense at all. Well, if it was a real number $r < 1,$ that real number would be greater than or equal to $sumlimits_{n=1}^{k} 9left( frac{1}{10} right)^{n}$ for any finite integer $k.$ This last number is the decimal $0.99 ldots 9 $ which terminates after $k$ occurrences of $9,$ and differs from $1$ by $frac{1}{10^{k}}.$ Since $0 < r <1,$ there is a value of $k$ such that $frac{1}{10^{k}} < 1-r,$ so $1 - frac{1}{10^{k}} >r.$ Hence $sumlimits_{n=1}^{k} 9left( frac{1}{10} right)^{n} > r.$ But this can't be, because we agreed that $r$ should be greater than or equal to each of those truncated sums.
Have I proved that the recurring decimal is equal to $1$? Not really- what I have proved is that if we allow that recurring decimal to meaningfully represent any real number, that real number has to be $1,$ since it can't be strictly less than $1$ and can't be strictly greater than $1$. At this point, it becomes a matter of convention to agree that the real number $1$ can be represented in that form, and that convention will be consistent with our usual operations with real numbers and ordering of the real numbers, and equating the expression with any other real number would not maintain that consistency.
edited Mar 11 at 15:29
community wiki
6 revs, 3 users 50%
Did
5
This is the best answer here; it's a shame it was posted four years later so it's gotten so little attention.
– Eric Wofsey
Oct 4 '15 at 0:44
1
If I am not mistaken then this answer also answers the question of this post.
– user 170039
Jan 6 '16 at 14:32
By the way, I was thinking that maybe you could write an answer for the linked post as well (or else, can you just tell me how can I give a link to this answer in a comment below my post?).
– user 170039
Jan 6 '16 at 14:40
1
I'm not sure how to set up links on here ( maybe the "cite") button. I am basically agreeing with what you say in your post.
– Geoff Robinson
Jan 6 '16 at 15:03
I think that the "evident" issue of a number being an abstract concept existing in isolation from any positional representation should also be explicitly stated. One then proceeds to give rules as to how the positional representation works (as you did), and from these rules it follows that all real numbers have an infinitely long representation in any base, and rational numbers have a finitely long representation in some bases. The integers are a special case of rational numbers that have a finite representation in all bases.
– Kuba Ober
Jul 28 '16 at 19:55
add a comment |
5
This is the best answer here; it's a shame it was posted four years later so it's gotten so little attention.
– Eric Wofsey
Oct 4 '15 at 0:44
1
If I am not mistaken then this answer also answers the question of this post.
– user 170039
Jan 6 '16 at 14:32
By the way, I was thinking that maybe you could write an answer for the linked post as well (or else, can you just tell me how can I give a link to this answer in a comment below my post?).
– user 170039
Jan 6 '16 at 14:40
1
I'm not sure how to set up links on here ( maybe the "cite") button. I am basically agreeing with what you say in your post.
– Geoff Robinson
Jan 6 '16 at 15:03
I think that the "evident" issue of a number being an abstract concept existing in isolation from any positional representation should also be explicitly stated. One then proceeds to give rules as to how the positional representation works (as you did), and from these rules it follows that all real numbers have an infinitely long representation in any base, and rational numbers have a finitely long representation in some bases. The integers are a special case of rational numbers that have a finite representation in all bases.
– Kuba Ober
Jul 28 '16 at 19:55
5
5
This is the best answer here; it's a shame it was posted four years later so it's gotten so little attention.
– Eric Wofsey
Oct 4 '15 at 0:44
This is the best answer here; it's a shame it was posted four years later so it's gotten so little attention.
– Eric Wofsey
Oct 4 '15 at 0:44
1
1
If I am not mistaken then this answer also answers the question of this post.
– user 170039
Jan 6 '16 at 14:32
If I am not mistaken then this answer also answers the question of this post.
– user 170039
Jan 6 '16 at 14:32
By the way, I was thinking that maybe you could write an answer for the linked post as well (or else, can you just tell me how can I give a link to this answer in a comment below my post?).
– user 170039
Jan 6 '16 at 14:40
By the way, I was thinking that maybe you could write an answer for the linked post as well (or else, can you just tell me how can I give a link to this answer in a comment below my post?).
– user 170039
Jan 6 '16 at 14:40
1
1
I'm not sure how to set up links on here ( maybe the "cite") button. I am basically agreeing with what you say in your post.
– Geoff Robinson
Jan 6 '16 at 15:03
I'm not sure how to set up links on here ( maybe the "cite") button. I am basically agreeing with what you say in your post.
– Geoff Robinson
Jan 6 '16 at 15:03
I think that the "evident" issue of a number being an abstract concept existing in isolation from any positional representation should also be explicitly stated. One then proceeds to give rules as to how the positional representation works (as you did), and from these rules it follows that all real numbers have an infinitely long representation in any base, and rational numbers have a finitely long representation in some bases. The integers are a special case of rational numbers that have a finite representation in all bases.
– Kuba Ober
Jul 28 '16 at 19:55
I think that the "evident" issue of a number being an abstract concept existing in isolation from any positional representation should also be explicitly stated. One then proceeds to give rules as to how the positional representation works (as you did), and from these rules it follows that all real numbers have an infinitely long representation in any base, and rational numbers have a finitely long representation in some bases. The integers are a special case of rational numbers that have a finite representation in all bases.
– Kuba Ober
Jul 28 '16 at 19:55
add a comment |
up vote
39
down vote
One argument against this is that 0.99999999... is "somewhat" less than 1. How much exactly?
1 - 0.999999... = ε (0)
If the above is true, the following also must be true:
9 × (1 - 0.999999...) = ε × 9
Let's calculate:
0.999... ×
9 =
───────────
8.1
81
81
.
.
.
───────────
8.999...
Thus:
9 - 8.999999... = 9ε (1)
But:
8.999999... = 8 + 0.99999... (2)
Indeed:
8.00000000... +
0.99999999... =
────────────────
8.99999999...
Now let's see what we can deduce from (0)
, (1)
and (2)
.
9 - 8.999999... = 9ε because of (2)
9 - 8.999999... = 9 - (8 + 0.99999...) = because of (1)
= 9 - 8 - (1 - ε) because of (0)
= 1 - 1 + ε
= ε.
Thus:
9ε = ε
8ε = 0
ε = 0
1 - 0.999999... = ε = 0
Quod erat demonstrandum. Pardon my unicode.
I did my best to avoid0.00000...
, but this made the calculations not as strikingly simple as I'd have liked to.
– badp
Jul 20 '10 at 21:10
Why was this voted down? It seems reasonable to this amateur math enjoyer.
– ErikE
Sep 25 '10 at 7:07
@Emtucifor I guess this sounds like "nonsense" to people that disagree on the basic premise of0.999... = 1
:)
– badp
Sep 25 '10 at 7:21
8ε = 0 instead of 10ε = 0
– user59671
May 9 '13 at 9:37
2
@SerjSagan nope, the RHS of (1) follows from (0). The fact that $9ε = ε$ is precisely the point I'm making.
– badp
Aug 2 '16 at 20:00
|
show 9 more comments
up vote
39
down vote
One argument against this is that 0.99999999... is "somewhat" less than 1. How much exactly?
1 - 0.999999... = ε (0)
If the above is true, the following also must be true:
9 × (1 - 0.999999...) = ε × 9
Let's calculate:
0.999... ×
9 =
───────────
8.1
81
81
.
.
.
───────────
8.999...
Thus:
9 - 8.999999... = 9ε (1)
But:
8.999999... = 8 + 0.99999... (2)
Indeed:
8.00000000... +
0.99999999... =
────────────────
8.99999999...
Now let's see what we can deduce from (0)
, (1)
and (2)
.
9 - 8.999999... = 9ε because of (2)
9 - 8.999999... = 9 - (8 + 0.99999...) = because of (1)
= 9 - 8 - (1 - ε) because of (0)
= 1 - 1 + ε
= ε.
Thus:
9ε = ε
8ε = 0
ε = 0
1 - 0.999999... = ε = 0
Quod erat demonstrandum. Pardon my unicode.
I did my best to avoid0.00000...
, but this made the calculations not as strikingly simple as I'd have liked to.
– badp
Jul 20 '10 at 21:10
Why was this voted down? It seems reasonable to this amateur math enjoyer.
– ErikE
Sep 25 '10 at 7:07
@Emtucifor I guess this sounds like "nonsense" to people that disagree on the basic premise of0.999... = 1
:)
– badp
Sep 25 '10 at 7:21
8ε = 0 instead of 10ε = 0
– user59671
May 9 '13 at 9:37
2
@SerjSagan nope, the RHS of (1) follows from (0). The fact that $9ε = ε$ is precisely the point I'm making.
– badp
Aug 2 '16 at 20:00
|
show 9 more comments
up vote
39
down vote
up vote
39
down vote
One argument against this is that 0.99999999... is "somewhat" less than 1. How much exactly?
1 - 0.999999... = ε (0)
If the above is true, the following also must be true:
9 × (1 - 0.999999...) = ε × 9
Let's calculate:
0.999... ×
9 =
───────────
8.1
81
81
.
.
.
───────────
8.999...
Thus:
9 - 8.999999... = 9ε (1)
But:
8.999999... = 8 + 0.99999... (2)
Indeed:
8.00000000... +
0.99999999... =
────────────────
8.99999999...
Now let's see what we can deduce from (0)
, (1)
and (2)
.
9 - 8.999999... = 9ε because of (2)
9 - 8.999999... = 9 - (8 + 0.99999...) = because of (1)
= 9 - 8 - (1 - ε) because of (0)
= 1 - 1 + ε
= ε.
Thus:
9ε = ε
8ε = 0
ε = 0
1 - 0.999999... = ε = 0
Quod erat demonstrandum. Pardon my unicode.
One argument against this is that 0.99999999... is "somewhat" less than 1. How much exactly?
1 - 0.999999... = ε (0)
If the above is true, the following also must be true:
9 × (1 - 0.999999...) = ε × 9
Let's calculate:
0.999... ×
9 =
───────────
8.1
81
81
.
.
.
───────────
8.999...
Thus:
9 - 8.999999... = 9ε (1)
But:
8.999999... = 8 + 0.99999... (2)
Indeed:
8.00000000... +
0.99999999... =
────────────────
8.99999999...
Now let's see what we can deduce from (0)
, (1)
and (2)
.
9 - 8.999999... = 9ε because of (2)
9 - 8.999999... = 9 - (8 + 0.99999...) = because of (1)
= 9 - 8 - (1 - ε) because of (0)
= 1 - 1 + ε
= ε.
Thus:
9ε = ε
8ε = 0
ε = 0
1 - 0.999999... = ε = 0
Quod erat demonstrandum. Pardon my unicode.
edited Apr 22 '14 at 9:38
community wiki
7 revs, 2 users 99%
badp
I did my best to avoid0.00000...
, but this made the calculations not as strikingly simple as I'd have liked to.
– badp
Jul 20 '10 at 21:10
Why was this voted down? It seems reasonable to this amateur math enjoyer.
– ErikE
Sep 25 '10 at 7:07
@Emtucifor I guess this sounds like "nonsense" to people that disagree on the basic premise of0.999... = 1
:)
– badp
Sep 25 '10 at 7:21
8ε = 0 instead of 10ε = 0
– user59671
May 9 '13 at 9:37
2
@SerjSagan nope, the RHS of (1) follows from (0). The fact that $9ε = ε$ is precisely the point I'm making.
– badp
Aug 2 '16 at 20:00
|
show 9 more comments
I did my best to avoid0.00000...
, but this made the calculations not as strikingly simple as I'd have liked to.
– badp
Jul 20 '10 at 21:10
Why was this voted down? It seems reasonable to this amateur math enjoyer.
– ErikE
Sep 25 '10 at 7:07
@Emtucifor I guess this sounds like "nonsense" to people that disagree on the basic premise of0.999... = 1
:)
– badp
Sep 25 '10 at 7:21
8ε = 0 instead of 10ε = 0
– user59671
May 9 '13 at 9:37
2
@SerjSagan nope, the RHS of (1) follows from (0). The fact that $9ε = ε$ is precisely the point I'm making.
– badp
Aug 2 '16 at 20:00
I did my best to avoid
0.00000...
, but this made the calculations not as strikingly simple as I'd have liked to.– badp
Jul 20 '10 at 21:10
I did my best to avoid
0.00000...
, but this made the calculations not as strikingly simple as I'd have liked to.– badp
Jul 20 '10 at 21:10
Why was this voted down? It seems reasonable to this amateur math enjoyer.
– ErikE
Sep 25 '10 at 7:07
Why was this voted down? It seems reasonable to this amateur math enjoyer.
– ErikE
Sep 25 '10 at 7:07
@Emtucifor I guess this sounds like "nonsense" to people that disagree on the basic premise of
0.999... = 1
:)– badp
Sep 25 '10 at 7:21
@Emtucifor I guess this sounds like "nonsense" to people that disagree on the basic premise of
0.999... = 1
:)– badp
Sep 25 '10 at 7:21
8ε = 0 instead of 10ε = 0
– user59671
May 9 '13 at 9:37
8ε = 0 instead of 10ε = 0
– user59671
May 9 '13 at 9:37
2
2
@SerjSagan nope, the RHS of (1) follows from (0). The fact that $9ε = ε$ is precisely the point I'm making.
– badp
Aug 2 '16 at 20:00
@SerjSagan nope, the RHS of (1) follows from (0). The fact that $9ε = ε$ is precisely the point I'm making.
– badp
Aug 2 '16 at 20:00
|
show 9 more comments
up vote
23
down vote
.999... = 1
because .999...
is a concise symbolic representation of "the limit of some variable as it approaches one." Therefore, .999... = 1
for the same reason the limit of x as x approaches 1 equals 1.
add a comment |
up vote
23
down vote
.999... = 1
because .999...
is a concise symbolic representation of "the limit of some variable as it approaches one." Therefore, .999... = 1
for the same reason the limit of x as x approaches 1 equals 1.
add a comment |
up vote
23
down vote
up vote
23
down vote
.999... = 1
because .999...
is a concise symbolic representation of "the limit of some variable as it approaches one." Therefore, .999... = 1
for the same reason the limit of x as x approaches 1 equals 1.
.999... = 1
because .999...
is a concise symbolic representation of "the limit of some variable as it approaches one." Therefore, .999... = 1
for the same reason the limit of x as x approaches 1 equals 1.
edited Jul 23 '10 at 2:13
community wiki
2 revs
Ami
add a comment |
add a comment |
up vote
18
down vote
If you take two real numbers x
and y
then there per definition of the real number z
for which x < z < y
or x > z > y
is true.
For x = 0.99999...
and y = 1
you can't find a z
and therefore 0.99999... = 1
.
add a comment |
up vote
18
down vote
If you take two real numbers x
and y
then there per definition of the real number z
for which x < z < y
or x > z > y
is true.
For x = 0.99999...
and y = 1
you can't find a z
and therefore 0.99999... = 1
.
add a comment |
up vote
18
down vote
up vote
18
down vote
If you take two real numbers x
and y
then there per definition of the real number z
for which x < z < y
or x > z > y
is true.
For x = 0.99999...
and y = 1
you can't find a z
and therefore 0.99999... = 1
.
If you take two real numbers x
and y
then there per definition of the real number z
for which x < z < y
or x > z > y
is true.
For x = 0.99999...
and y = 1
you can't find a z
and therefore 0.99999... = 1
.
edited Jul 20 '10 at 23:50
community wiki
2 revs
Christian
add a comment |
add a comment |
up vote
15
down vote
You can visualise it by thinking about it in infinitesimals. The more $9's$ you have on the end of $0.999$, the closer you get to $1$. When you add an infinite number of $9's$ to the decimal expansion, you are infinitely close to $1$ (or an infinitesimal distance away).
And this isn't a rigorous proof, just an aid to visualisation of the result.
I think this answer is not needed. It's similar to another answer but has wrong information. Infinitesimal numbers exist only in the hyperreal number system and in the hyperreal system, numbers infinitesimally close are not equal. The real numbers are a subset of the hyperreal numbers so the community decided theat the notation represents 1 and not a number infinitesimally close because then it wouldn't represent a real number. Maybe the real numbers can be defined as equivalence classes infinitesimally close hyperreal numbers and from that, redefine the notation to represent the number 1.
– Timothy
May 22 at 19:19
add a comment |
up vote
15
down vote
You can visualise it by thinking about it in infinitesimals. The more $9's$ you have on the end of $0.999$, the closer you get to $1$. When you add an infinite number of $9's$ to the decimal expansion, you are infinitely close to $1$ (or an infinitesimal distance away).
And this isn't a rigorous proof, just an aid to visualisation of the result.
I think this answer is not needed. It's similar to another answer but has wrong information. Infinitesimal numbers exist only in the hyperreal number system and in the hyperreal system, numbers infinitesimally close are not equal. The real numbers are a subset of the hyperreal numbers so the community decided theat the notation represents 1 and not a number infinitesimally close because then it wouldn't represent a real number. Maybe the real numbers can be defined as equivalence classes infinitesimally close hyperreal numbers and from that, redefine the notation to represent the number 1.
– Timothy
May 22 at 19:19
add a comment |
up vote
15
down vote
up vote
15
down vote
You can visualise it by thinking about it in infinitesimals. The more $9's$ you have on the end of $0.999$, the closer you get to $1$. When you add an infinite number of $9's$ to the decimal expansion, you are infinitely close to $1$ (or an infinitesimal distance away).
And this isn't a rigorous proof, just an aid to visualisation of the result.
You can visualise it by thinking about it in infinitesimals. The more $9's$ you have on the end of $0.999$, the closer you get to $1$. When you add an infinite number of $9's$ to the decimal expansion, you are infinitely close to $1$ (or an infinitesimal distance away).
And this isn't a rigorous proof, just an aid to visualisation of the result.
edited May 6 '16 at 18:24
community wiki
2 revs, 2 users 80%
workmad3
I think this answer is not needed. It's similar to another answer but has wrong information. Infinitesimal numbers exist only in the hyperreal number system and in the hyperreal system, numbers infinitesimally close are not equal. The real numbers are a subset of the hyperreal numbers so the community decided theat the notation represents 1 and not a number infinitesimally close because then it wouldn't represent a real number. Maybe the real numbers can be defined as equivalence classes infinitesimally close hyperreal numbers and from that, redefine the notation to represent the number 1.
– Timothy
May 22 at 19:19
add a comment |
I think this answer is not needed. It's similar to another answer but has wrong information. Infinitesimal numbers exist only in the hyperreal number system and in the hyperreal system, numbers infinitesimally close are not equal. The real numbers are a subset of the hyperreal numbers so the community decided theat the notation represents 1 and not a number infinitesimally close because then it wouldn't represent a real number. Maybe the real numbers can be defined as equivalence classes infinitesimally close hyperreal numbers and from that, redefine the notation to represent the number 1.
– Timothy
May 22 at 19:19
I think this answer is not needed. It's similar to another answer but has wrong information. Infinitesimal numbers exist only in the hyperreal number system and in the hyperreal system, numbers infinitesimally close are not equal. The real numbers are a subset of the hyperreal numbers so the community decided theat the notation represents 1 and not a number infinitesimally close because then it wouldn't represent a real number. Maybe the real numbers can be defined as equivalence classes infinitesimally close hyperreal numbers and from that, redefine the notation to represent the number 1.
– Timothy
May 22 at 19:19
I think this answer is not needed. It's similar to another answer but has wrong information. Infinitesimal numbers exist only in the hyperreal number system and in the hyperreal system, numbers infinitesimally close are not equal. The real numbers are a subset of the hyperreal numbers so the community decided theat the notation represents 1 and not a number infinitesimally close because then it wouldn't represent a real number. Maybe the real numbers can be defined as equivalence classes infinitesimally close hyperreal numbers and from that, redefine the notation to represent the number 1.
– Timothy
May 22 at 19:19
add a comment |
up vote
12
down vote
Indeed this is true. The underlying reason is that decimal numbers are not unique representations of the reals. (Technically, there does not exist a bijection between the set of all decimal numbers and the reals.)
Here's a very simple proof:
$$begin{align}
frac13&=0.333ldots&hbox{(by long division)}\
implies0.333ldotstimes3&=0.999ldots&hbox{(multiplying each digit by $3$)}
end{align}$$
Then we already know $0.333ldotstimes3=1$ therefore $0.999ldots=1$.
22
-1. This is not a proof at all! Why is 1/3=0.333...? Seriously folks, for the private beta, let's try to maintain a little correctiness.
– Scott Morrison
Jul 20 '10 at 20:03
5
@Scott: Sure it is. You can prove it easily by long division. This is about algorithms for mathematical methods really.
– Noldorin
Jul 20 '10 at 20:12
6
@Scott: Might help to stop whining and post what you think is the 'correct' answer then.
– Noldorin
Jul 20 '10 at 20:17
11
Just to nitpick, there is a bijection between the set of decimal expansions and reals because they are sets with the same cardinality. It's just that the natural map taking expansions to real numbers isn't injective.
– Simon Nickerson
Jul 20 '10 at 21:15
3
@Scott, I see it would not be obvious that 1/3=0.333..., but as by Noldorins comment regarding long division, what would be wrong with this as a proof, if the first line is annotated with 'by long division' ?
– Sami
Jul 21 '10 at 4:58
|
show 11 more comments
up vote
12
down vote
Indeed this is true. The underlying reason is that decimal numbers are not unique representations of the reals. (Technically, there does not exist a bijection between the set of all decimal numbers and the reals.)
Here's a very simple proof:
$$begin{align}
frac13&=0.333ldots&hbox{(by long division)}\
implies0.333ldotstimes3&=0.999ldots&hbox{(multiplying each digit by $3$)}
end{align}$$
Then we already know $0.333ldotstimes3=1$ therefore $0.999ldots=1$.
22
-1. This is not a proof at all! Why is 1/3=0.333...? Seriously folks, for the private beta, let's try to maintain a little correctiness.
– Scott Morrison
Jul 20 '10 at 20:03
5
@Scott: Sure it is. You can prove it easily by long division. This is about algorithms for mathematical methods really.
– Noldorin
Jul 20 '10 at 20:12
6
@Scott: Might help to stop whining and post what you think is the 'correct' answer then.
– Noldorin
Jul 20 '10 at 20:17
11
Just to nitpick, there is a bijection between the set of decimal expansions and reals because they are sets with the same cardinality. It's just that the natural map taking expansions to real numbers isn't injective.
– Simon Nickerson
Jul 20 '10 at 21:15
3
@Scott, I see it would not be obvious that 1/3=0.333..., but as by Noldorins comment regarding long division, what would be wrong with this as a proof, if the first line is annotated with 'by long division' ?
– Sami
Jul 21 '10 at 4:58
|
show 11 more comments
up vote
12
down vote
up vote
12
down vote
Indeed this is true. The underlying reason is that decimal numbers are not unique representations of the reals. (Technically, there does not exist a bijection between the set of all decimal numbers and the reals.)
Here's a very simple proof:
$$begin{align}
frac13&=0.333ldots&hbox{(by long division)}\
implies0.333ldotstimes3&=0.999ldots&hbox{(multiplying each digit by $3$)}
end{align}$$
Then we already know $0.333ldotstimes3=1$ therefore $0.999ldots=1$.
Indeed this is true. The underlying reason is that decimal numbers are not unique representations of the reals. (Technically, there does not exist a bijection between the set of all decimal numbers and the reals.)
Here's a very simple proof:
$$begin{align}
frac13&=0.333ldots&hbox{(by long division)}\
implies0.333ldotstimes3&=0.999ldots&hbox{(multiplying each digit by $3$)}
end{align}$$
Then we already know $0.333ldotstimes3=1$ therefore $0.999ldots=1$.
edited Feb 24 '17 at 20:51
community wiki
3 revs, 2 users 77%
Noldorin
22
-1. This is not a proof at all! Why is 1/3=0.333...? Seriously folks, for the private beta, let's try to maintain a little correctiness.
– Scott Morrison
Jul 20 '10 at 20:03
5
@Scott: Sure it is. You can prove it easily by long division. This is about algorithms for mathematical methods really.
– Noldorin
Jul 20 '10 at 20:12
6
@Scott: Might help to stop whining and post what you think is the 'correct' answer then.
– Noldorin
Jul 20 '10 at 20:17
11
Just to nitpick, there is a bijection between the set of decimal expansions and reals because they are sets with the same cardinality. It's just that the natural map taking expansions to real numbers isn't injective.
– Simon Nickerson
Jul 20 '10 at 21:15
3
@Scott, I see it would not be obvious that 1/3=0.333..., but as by Noldorins comment regarding long division, what would be wrong with this as a proof, if the first line is annotated with 'by long division' ?
– Sami
Jul 21 '10 at 4:58
|
show 11 more comments
22
-1. This is not a proof at all! Why is 1/3=0.333...? Seriously folks, for the private beta, let's try to maintain a little correctiness.
– Scott Morrison
Jul 20 '10 at 20:03
5
@Scott: Sure it is. You can prove it easily by long division. This is about algorithms for mathematical methods really.
– Noldorin
Jul 20 '10 at 20:12
6
@Scott: Might help to stop whining and post what you think is the 'correct' answer then.
– Noldorin
Jul 20 '10 at 20:17
11
Just to nitpick, there is a bijection between the set of decimal expansions and reals because they are sets with the same cardinality. It's just that the natural map taking expansions to real numbers isn't injective.
– Simon Nickerson
Jul 20 '10 at 21:15
3
@Scott, I see it would not be obvious that 1/3=0.333..., but as by Noldorins comment regarding long division, what would be wrong with this as a proof, if the first line is annotated with 'by long division' ?
– Sami
Jul 21 '10 at 4:58
22
22
-1. This is not a proof at all! Why is 1/3=0.333...? Seriously folks, for the private beta, let's try to maintain a little correctiness.
– Scott Morrison
Jul 20 '10 at 20:03
-1. This is not a proof at all! Why is 1/3=0.333...? Seriously folks, for the private beta, let's try to maintain a little correctiness.
– Scott Morrison
Jul 20 '10 at 20:03
5
5
@Scott: Sure it is. You can prove it easily by long division. This is about algorithms for mathematical methods really.
– Noldorin
Jul 20 '10 at 20:12
@Scott: Sure it is. You can prove it easily by long division. This is about algorithms for mathematical methods really.
– Noldorin
Jul 20 '10 at 20:12
6
6
@Scott: Might help to stop whining and post what you think is the 'correct' answer then.
– Noldorin
Jul 20 '10 at 20:17
@Scott: Might help to stop whining and post what you think is the 'correct' answer then.
– Noldorin
Jul 20 '10 at 20:17
11
11
Just to nitpick, there is a bijection between the set of decimal expansions and reals because they are sets with the same cardinality. It's just that the natural map taking expansions to real numbers isn't injective.
– Simon Nickerson
Jul 20 '10 at 21:15
Just to nitpick, there is a bijection between the set of decimal expansions and reals because they are sets with the same cardinality. It's just that the natural map taking expansions to real numbers isn't injective.
– Simon Nickerson
Jul 20 '10 at 21:15
3
3
@Scott, I see it would not be obvious that 1/3=0.333..., but as by Noldorins comment regarding long division, what would be wrong with this as a proof, if the first line is annotated with 'by long division' ?
– Sami
Jul 21 '10 at 4:58
@Scott, I see it would not be obvious that 1/3=0.333..., but as by Noldorins comment regarding long division, what would be wrong with this as a proof, if the first line is annotated with 'by long division' ?
– Sami
Jul 21 '10 at 4:58
|
show 11 more comments
up vote
11
down vote
Given (by long division):
$frac{1}{3} = 0.bar{3}$
Multiply by 3:
$3times left( frac{1}{3} right) = left( 0.bar{3} right) times 3$
Therefore:
$frac{3}{3} = 0.bar{9}$
QED.
I think the long division precisely involves the proof of a limit like the sum mentioned above...
– C-Star-Puppy
Aug 27 '14 at 21:07
1
@FreeziiS, for this particular question the fact of a rigorous proof happens to be less important than the fact of a convincing proof. Plenty of people trust the long division algorithm because they learned it in school; they haven't seen a rigorous proof for its workability because they don't care; it obviously works. It is these people (who don't care about or trust rigorous proofs) who argue the most about $0.999999...$
– Wildcard
Dec 20 '16 at 0:16
add a comment |
up vote
11
down vote
Given (by long division):
$frac{1}{3} = 0.bar{3}$
Multiply by 3:
$3times left( frac{1}{3} right) = left( 0.bar{3} right) times 3$
Therefore:
$frac{3}{3} = 0.bar{9}$
QED.
I think the long division precisely involves the proof of a limit like the sum mentioned above...
– C-Star-Puppy
Aug 27 '14 at 21:07
1
@FreeziiS, for this particular question the fact of a rigorous proof happens to be less important than the fact of a convincing proof. Plenty of people trust the long division algorithm because they learned it in school; they haven't seen a rigorous proof for its workability because they don't care; it obviously works. It is these people (who don't care about or trust rigorous proofs) who argue the most about $0.999999...$
– Wildcard
Dec 20 '16 at 0:16
add a comment |
up vote
11
down vote
up vote
11
down vote
Given (by long division):
$frac{1}{3} = 0.bar{3}$
Multiply by 3:
$3times left( frac{1}{3} right) = left( 0.bar{3} right) times 3$
Therefore:
$frac{3}{3} = 0.bar{9}$
QED.
Given (by long division):
$frac{1}{3} = 0.bar{3}$
Multiply by 3:
$3times left( frac{1}{3} right) = left( 0.bar{3} right) times 3$
Therefore:
$frac{3}{3} = 0.bar{9}$
QED.
edited Feb 21 '11 at 2:52
community wiki
3 revs
John Gietzen
I think the long division precisely involves the proof of a limit like the sum mentioned above...
– C-Star-Puppy
Aug 27 '14 at 21:07
1
@FreeziiS, for this particular question the fact of a rigorous proof happens to be less important than the fact of a convincing proof. Plenty of people trust the long division algorithm because they learned it in school; they haven't seen a rigorous proof for its workability because they don't care; it obviously works. It is these people (who don't care about or trust rigorous proofs) who argue the most about $0.999999...$
– Wildcard
Dec 20 '16 at 0:16
add a comment |
I think the long division precisely involves the proof of a limit like the sum mentioned above...
– C-Star-Puppy
Aug 27 '14 at 21:07
1
@FreeziiS, for this particular question the fact of a rigorous proof happens to be less important than the fact of a convincing proof. Plenty of people trust the long division algorithm because they learned it in school; they haven't seen a rigorous proof for its workability because they don't care; it obviously works. It is these people (who don't care about or trust rigorous proofs) who argue the most about $0.999999...$
– Wildcard
Dec 20 '16 at 0:16
I think the long division precisely involves the proof of a limit like the sum mentioned above...
– C-Star-Puppy
Aug 27 '14 at 21:07
I think the long division precisely involves the proof of a limit like the sum mentioned above...
– C-Star-Puppy
Aug 27 '14 at 21:07
1
1
@FreeziiS, for this particular question the fact of a rigorous proof happens to be less important than the fact of a convincing proof. Plenty of people trust the long division algorithm because they learned it in school; they haven't seen a rigorous proof for its workability because they don't care; it obviously works. It is these people (who don't care about or trust rigorous proofs) who argue the most about $0.999999...$
– Wildcard
Dec 20 '16 at 0:16
@FreeziiS, for this particular question the fact of a rigorous proof happens to be less important than the fact of a convincing proof. Plenty of people trust the long division algorithm because they learned it in school; they haven't seen a rigorous proof for its workability because they don't care; it obviously works. It is these people (who don't care about or trust rigorous proofs) who argue the most about $0.999999...$
– Wildcard
Dec 20 '16 at 0:16
add a comment |
up vote
9
down vote
Often times people who ask this question are not very convinced by a proof. Since they may not be particularly math inclined, they may feel that a proof is a sort of sleight-of-hand trick, and I find the following intuitive argument (read "don't down-vote me for lack of rigor, lack of rigor is the point") a bit more convincing:
STEP 1) If $.99...neq1$, everyone agrees that it must be less than $1$. Let $alpha$ denote $.99...$, this mysterious number less than $1$.
STEP 2) Using a number line, you can convince them that since $alpha<1$, there must be another number $beta$ such that $alpha<beta<1$.
STEP 3) Since $alpha<beta$, one of the digits of $beta$ must be bigger than the corresponding digit of $alpha$.
STEP 4) However it is usually intitively clear that you cannot make any digit of $.99...$ bigger without making the resulting number (ie $beta$) bigger than $1$.
STEP 5) Thus no such $beta$ can exist, and thus $.99...$ cannot be less than $1$.
add a comment |
up vote
9
down vote
Often times people who ask this question are not very convinced by a proof. Since they may not be particularly math inclined, they may feel that a proof is a sort of sleight-of-hand trick, and I find the following intuitive argument (read "don't down-vote me for lack of rigor, lack of rigor is the point") a bit more convincing:
STEP 1) If $.99...neq1$, everyone agrees that it must be less than $1$. Let $alpha$ denote $.99...$, this mysterious number less than $1$.
STEP 2) Using a number line, you can convince them that since $alpha<1$, there must be another number $beta$ such that $alpha<beta<1$.
STEP 3) Since $alpha<beta$, one of the digits of $beta$ must be bigger than the corresponding digit of $alpha$.
STEP 4) However it is usually intitively clear that you cannot make any digit of $.99...$ bigger without making the resulting number (ie $beta$) bigger than $1$.
STEP 5) Thus no such $beta$ can exist, and thus $.99...$ cannot be less than $1$.
add a comment |
up vote
9
down vote
up vote
9
down vote
Often times people who ask this question are not very convinced by a proof. Since they may not be particularly math inclined, they may feel that a proof is a sort of sleight-of-hand trick, and I find the following intuitive argument (read "don't down-vote me for lack of rigor, lack of rigor is the point") a bit more convincing:
STEP 1) If $.99...neq1$, everyone agrees that it must be less than $1$. Let $alpha$ denote $.99...$, this mysterious number less than $1$.
STEP 2) Using a number line, you can convince them that since $alpha<1$, there must be another number $beta$ such that $alpha<beta<1$.
STEP 3) Since $alpha<beta$, one of the digits of $beta$ must be bigger than the corresponding digit of $alpha$.
STEP 4) However it is usually intitively clear that you cannot make any digit of $.99...$ bigger without making the resulting number (ie $beta$) bigger than $1$.
STEP 5) Thus no such $beta$ can exist, and thus $.99...$ cannot be less than $1$.
Often times people who ask this question are not very convinced by a proof. Since they may not be particularly math inclined, they may feel that a proof is a sort of sleight-of-hand trick, and I find the following intuitive argument (read "don't down-vote me for lack of rigor, lack of rigor is the point") a bit more convincing:
STEP 1) If $.99...neq1$, everyone agrees that it must be less than $1$. Let $alpha$ denote $.99...$, this mysterious number less than $1$.
STEP 2) Using a number line, you can convince them that since $alpha<1$, there must be another number $beta$ such that $alpha<beta<1$.
STEP 3) Since $alpha<beta$, one of the digits of $beta$ must be bigger than the corresponding digit of $alpha$.
STEP 4) However it is usually intitively clear that you cannot make any digit of $.99...$ bigger without making the resulting number (ie $beta$) bigger than $1$.
STEP 5) Thus no such $beta$ can exist, and thus $.99...$ cannot be less than $1$.
answered Sep 15 '14 at 14:39
community wiki
Trevor Richards
add a comment |
add a comment |
up vote
7
down vote
The real number system is defined as an extension of the rationals with the property that any sequence with an upper bound has a LEAST upper bound. The expression " 0.9-repeated" is defined to be the least real-number upper bound of the sequence 0.9. 0.99, 0.999,..... , which is 1. The rationals (and the reals) can also be extended to an arithmetic system (an ordered field) in which there are positive values which are less than every positive rational. In such systems the expression ".9-repeated" has no meaning.
add a comment |
up vote
7
down vote
The real number system is defined as an extension of the rationals with the property that any sequence with an upper bound has a LEAST upper bound. The expression " 0.9-repeated" is defined to be the least real-number upper bound of the sequence 0.9. 0.99, 0.999,..... , which is 1. The rationals (and the reals) can also be extended to an arithmetic system (an ordered field) in which there are positive values which are less than every positive rational. In such systems the expression ".9-repeated" has no meaning.
add a comment |
up vote
7
down vote
up vote
7
down vote
The real number system is defined as an extension of the rationals with the property that any sequence with an upper bound has a LEAST upper bound. The expression " 0.9-repeated" is defined to be the least real-number upper bound of the sequence 0.9. 0.99, 0.999,..... , which is 1. The rationals (and the reals) can also be extended to an arithmetic system (an ordered field) in which there are positive values which are less than every positive rational. In such systems the expression ".9-repeated" has no meaning.
The real number system is defined as an extension of the rationals with the property that any sequence with an upper bound has a LEAST upper bound. The expression " 0.9-repeated" is defined to be the least real-number upper bound of the sequence 0.9. 0.99, 0.999,..... , which is 1. The rationals (and the reals) can also be extended to an arithmetic system (an ordered field) in which there are positive values which are less than every positive rational. In such systems the expression ".9-repeated" has no meaning.
answered Jul 16 '15 at 5:37
community wiki
DanielWainfleet
add a comment |
add a comment |
up vote
7
down vote
The problem isn't proving that $0.9999... = 1$. There are many proofs and they all are easy.
The problem is being convinced that every argument you are making actually is valid and makes sense, and not having a sinking feeling you aren't just falling for some parlor trick.
$0.99...9;$ (with $n$ 9s) is $sum_{i= 1}^n frac 9 {10^i}$ so "obviously" $0.999....$ (with an infinite number of 9s) is $sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac 9{10^i}$.
The obvious objection is: does it even make sense to talk about adding an infinite number of terms? How can we talk about taking and adding an infinite number of terms?
And it's a legitimate objection.
So when we learn math in elementary school we are told: Every real number can be written as a decimal expansion (maybe infinite) and every possible decimal expansion is a real number. And this is true. But we are not told why and we are expected to take it on faith, and we usually do.
IF we take this on faith then a proof is very easy:
$0.9999.... = sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac 9{10^i}$
$10*(0.9999....) = 10*sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac 9{10^i}= sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac {90}{10^i}=$
$sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac 9{10^{i-1}} = 9/10^0 + sum_{i = 2}^{infty} frac 9{10^{i-1}}= 9 + sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac 9{10^i}$ (Look at the indexes!)
So...
$10*(0.999...) - (0.9999...) = (10 - 1)*0.9999.... = 9*0.99999.... = $
$9 + sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac 9{10^i} - sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac 9{10^i} = 9$.
So...
$0.9999.... = 9/9 = 1$.
Easy! !!!!!!!IF!!!!!!! we take it on faith that: Every real number can be written as a decimal expansion (maybe infinite) and every possible decimal expansion is a real number.
So why can we take that on faith? That's the issue: why is that true and what does it mean?
So....
We've got the Integers. We use them to count discrete measurements. We can use an integer to divide a unit 1 into $m$ sub-units to measure measurements of $1/m$. As the $m$ can be as large as we want the $1/m$ can be as precise as we want and the system of all possible $n/m; m ne 0$ can measure any possible quantity with arbitrary and infinite precision.
We hope. We call these $n/m$ numbers the Rationals and everything is fine until we discover that we can't actually measure measurements such as the square root of two or pi.
But the Rationals still have infinite precision. We can get within 1/10 away from pi. We can get within 1/100 away from pi. Within $1/10^n$ for any possible power of 10.
At this point, we hope we can say "we can't measure it with any finite power of 10 but we can always go one more significant measure, so if we go through infinite powers of 10 we will measure it to precision" and we hope that explanation will be convincing.
But it isn't really. We have these "missing numbers" and we can get infinitely close the them, but what are they really?
Well, we decide to become math majors and in our senior year of college we take a Real Analysis course and we find out.
We can view numbers as sets of rational numbers. We can split the rational numbers at any point into two sets. We can split the rational numbers so that all the rational numbers less than 1/2 are in set A and all the rational numbers greater than or equal to 1/2 are in set B (which we ignore; we are only interested in set A.)
These "cuts" can occur at any point but they must follow the following rules:
--the set A of all the smaller rational numbers is not empty. Nor does it contain every rational number. Some rational number is not in it.
--if any rational number (call it q) is in A, then every rational number smaller than q is also in A. (This means that if r is a rational not in A, then every rational bigger than r is also not in A.)
-- A does not have a single largest element. (So it can be all the elements less than 1/2 but it can't be all the elements less than or equal to 1/2).
And we let $overline R$ be the collection of all possible ways to "cut" the rational numbers in half that way.
Notice sometimes the cut will occur at a rational number (all the rationals less than 1/2), but sometimes it will occur at points "between" the rational numbers. (All the rationals whose squares are less than 2). So the collection $overline R$ is a larger set than the set of Rational numbers.
It turns out we can define the Real numbers as the points of $overline R$ where we can cut the rationals in two.
We need to do a bit or work to show that this is actually a number system. We say $x, y in overline R; x < y$ if the "Set A made by cutting at x" $subset$ "Set A made by cutting at y". And we say $x + y = $ the point where we need to cut so that the set A created contains all the sums of the two other sets created by cutting at x and y. And we have to prove math works on $overline R$. But we can do it. And we do.
But as a consequence we see that every real number is the least upper bound limit of a sequence of rational numbers. That's pretty much the definition of what a "cut point" is; the point that separate all the rationals less than it from all the other rationals.
I like to say (somewhat trivially) that: the real number $x$ is the least upper bound of all the rational numbers that are smaller than $x$. And it's true!
In the real numbers, every real number is the limit of some sequence of rational numbers. And every bounded sequence of rational numbers will have a real number least upper bound limit.
...
Let that sink in for a minute.
=====
Okay, so given a sequence {3, 3.1, 3.14, 3.141,....} = {finite decimals that are less than pi} is a bounded sequence of rational numbers so $pi = $ the limit of the sequence which is also the limit of the infinite sequence 3.1415926....
It now makes sense to talk of $0.9999.... = sum_{i=1}^{infty}9/10^i = lim{sum_{i=1}^n9/10^i}$ = a precise and real number.
And from there we can say with confidence that that number is $1$. (By any of these proofs.)
add a comment |
up vote
7
down vote
The problem isn't proving that $0.9999... = 1$. There are many proofs and they all are easy.
The problem is being convinced that every argument you are making actually is valid and makes sense, and not having a sinking feeling you aren't just falling for some parlor trick.
$0.99...9;$ (with $n$ 9s) is $sum_{i= 1}^n frac 9 {10^i}$ so "obviously" $0.999....$ (with an infinite number of 9s) is $sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac 9{10^i}$.
The obvious objection is: does it even make sense to talk about adding an infinite number of terms? How can we talk about taking and adding an infinite number of terms?
And it's a legitimate objection.
So when we learn math in elementary school we are told: Every real number can be written as a decimal expansion (maybe infinite) and every possible decimal expansion is a real number. And this is true. But we are not told why and we are expected to take it on faith, and we usually do.
IF we take this on faith then a proof is very easy:
$0.9999.... = sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac 9{10^i}$
$10*(0.9999....) = 10*sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac 9{10^i}= sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac {90}{10^i}=$
$sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac 9{10^{i-1}} = 9/10^0 + sum_{i = 2}^{infty} frac 9{10^{i-1}}= 9 + sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac 9{10^i}$ (Look at the indexes!)
So...
$10*(0.999...) - (0.9999...) = (10 - 1)*0.9999.... = 9*0.99999.... = $
$9 + sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac 9{10^i} - sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac 9{10^i} = 9$.
So...
$0.9999.... = 9/9 = 1$.
Easy! !!!!!!!IF!!!!!!! we take it on faith that: Every real number can be written as a decimal expansion (maybe infinite) and every possible decimal expansion is a real number.
So why can we take that on faith? That's the issue: why is that true and what does it mean?
So....
We've got the Integers. We use them to count discrete measurements. We can use an integer to divide a unit 1 into $m$ sub-units to measure measurements of $1/m$. As the $m$ can be as large as we want the $1/m$ can be as precise as we want and the system of all possible $n/m; m ne 0$ can measure any possible quantity with arbitrary and infinite precision.
We hope. We call these $n/m$ numbers the Rationals and everything is fine until we discover that we can't actually measure measurements such as the square root of two or pi.
But the Rationals still have infinite precision. We can get within 1/10 away from pi. We can get within 1/100 away from pi. Within $1/10^n$ for any possible power of 10.
At this point, we hope we can say "we can't measure it with any finite power of 10 but we can always go one more significant measure, so if we go through infinite powers of 10 we will measure it to precision" and we hope that explanation will be convincing.
But it isn't really. We have these "missing numbers" and we can get infinitely close the them, but what are they really?
Well, we decide to become math majors and in our senior year of college we take a Real Analysis course and we find out.
We can view numbers as sets of rational numbers. We can split the rational numbers at any point into two sets. We can split the rational numbers so that all the rational numbers less than 1/2 are in set A and all the rational numbers greater than or equal to 1/2 are in set B (which we ignore; we are only interested in set A.)
These "cuts" can occur at any point but they must follow the following rules:
--the set A of all the smaller rational numbers is not empty. Nor does it contain every rational number. Some rational number is not in it.
--if any rational number (call it q) is in A, then every rational number smaller than q is also in A. (This means that if r is a rational not in A, then every rational bigger than r is also not in A.)
-- A does not have a single largest element. (So it can be all the elements less than 1/2 but it can't be all the elements less than or equal to 1/2).
And we let $overline R$ be the collection of all possible ways to "cut" the rational numbers in half that way.
Notice sometimes the cut will occur at a rational number (all the rationals less than 1/2), but sometimes it will occur at points "between" the rational numbers. (All the rationals whose squares are less than 2). So the collection $overline R$ is a larger set than the set of Rational numbers.
It turns out we can define the Real numbers as the points of $overline R$ where we can cut the rationals in two.
We need to do a bit or work to show that this is actually a number system. We say $x, y in overline R; x < y$ if the "Set A made by cutting at x" $subset$ "Set A made by cutting at y". And we say $x + y = $ the point where we need to cut so that the set A created contains all the sums of the two other sets created by cutting at x and y. And we have to prove math works on $overline R$. But we can do it. And we do.
But as a consequence we see that every real number is the least upper bound limit of a sequence of rational numbers. That's pretty much the definition of what a "cut point" is; the point that separate all the rationals less than it from all the other rationals.
I like to say (somewhat trivially) that: the real number $x$ is the least upper bound of all the rational numbers that are smaller than $x$. And it's true!
In the real numbers, every real number is the limit of some sequence of rational numbers. And every bounded sequence of rational numbers will have a real number least upper bound limit.
...
Let that sink in for a minute.
=====
Okay, so given a sequence {3, 3.1, 3.14, 3.141,....} = {finite decimals that are less than pi} is a bounded sequence of rational numbers so $pi = $ the limit of the sequence which is also the limit of the infinite sequence 3.1415926....
It now makes sense to talk of $0.9999.... = sum_{i=1}^{infty}9/10^i = lim{sum_{i=1}^n9/10^i}$ = a precise and real number.
And from there we can say with confidence that that number is $1$. (By any of these proofs.)
add a comment |
up vote
7
down vote
up vote
7
down vote
The problem isn't proving that $0.9999... = 1$. There are many proofs and they all are easy.
The problem is being convinced that every argument you are making actually is valid and makes sense, and not having a sinking feeling you aren't just falling for some parlor trick.
$0.99...9;$ (with $n$ 9s) is $sum_{i= 1}^n frac 9 {10^i}$ so "obviously" $0.999....$ (with an infinite number of 9s) is $sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac 9{10^i}$.
The obvious objection is: does it even make sense to talk about adding an infinite number of terms? How can we talk about taking and adding an infinite number of terms?
And it's a legitimate objection.
So when we learn math in elementary school we are told: Every real number can be written as a decimal expansion (maybe infinite) and every possible decimal expansion is a real number. And this is true. But we are not told why and we are expected to take it on faith, and we usually do.
IF we take this on faith then a proof is very easy:
$0.9999.... = sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac 9{10^i}$
$10*(0.9999....) = 10*sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac 9{10^i}= sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac {90}{10^i}=$
$sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac 9{10^{i-1}} = 9/10^0 + sum_{i = 2}^{infty} frac 9{10^{i-1}}= 9 + sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac 9{10^i}$ (Look at the indexes!)
So...
$10*(0.999...) - (0.9999...) = (10 - 1)*0.9999.... = 9*0.99999.... = $
$9 + sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac 9{10^i} - sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac 9{10^i} = 9$.
So...
$0.9999.... = 9/9 = 1$.
Easy! !!!!!!!IF!!!!!!! we take it on faith that: Every real number can be written as a decimal expansion (maybe infinite) and every possible decimal expansion is a real number.
So why can we take that on faith? That's the issue: why is that true and what does it mean?
So....
We've got the Integers. We use them to count discrete measurements. We can use an integer to divide a unit 1 into $m$ sub-units to measure measurements of $1/m$. As the $m$ can be as large as we want the $1/m$ can be as precise as we want and the system of all possible $n/m; m ne 0$ can measure any possible quantity with arbitrary and infinite precision.
We hope. We call these $n/m$ numbers the Rationals and everything is fine until we discover that we can't actually measure measurements such as the square root of two or pi.
But the Rationals still have infinite precision. We can get within 1/10 away from pi. We can get within 1/100 away from pi. Within $1/10^n$ for any possible power of 10.
At this point, we hope we can say "we can't measure it with any finite power of 10 but we can always go one more significant measure, so if we go through infinite powers of 10 we will measure it to precision" and we hope that explanation will be convincing.
But it isn't really. We have these "missing numbers" and we can get infinitely close the them, but what are they really?
Well, we decide to become math majors and in our senior year of college we take a Real Analysis course and we find out.
We can view numbers as sets of rational numbers. We can split the rational numbers at any point into two sets. We can split the rational numbers so that all the rational numbers less than 1/2 are in set A and all the rational numbers greater than or equal to 1/2 are in set B (which we ignore; we are only interested in set A.)
These "cuts" can occur at any point but they must follow the following rules:
--the set A of all the smaller rational numbers is not empty. Nor does it contain every rational number. Some rational number is not in it.
--if any rational number (call it q) is in A, then every rational number smaller than q is also in A. (This means that if r is a rational not in A, then every rational bigger than r is also not in A.)
-- A does not have a single largest element. (So it can be all the elements less than 1/2 but it can't be all the elements less than or equal to 1/2).
And we let $overline R$ be the collection of all possible ways to "cut" the rational numbers in half that way.
Notice sometimes the cut will occur at a rational number (all the rationals less than 1/2), but sometimes it will occur at points "between" the rational numbers. (All the rationals whose squares are less than 2). So the collection $overline R$ is a larger set than the set of Rational numbers.
It turns out we can define the Real numbers as the points of $overline R$ where we can cut the rationals in two.
We need to do a bit or work to show that this is actually a number system. We say $x, y in overline R; x < y$ if the "Set A made by cutting at x" $subset$ "Set A made by cutting at y". And we say $x + y = $ the point where we need to cut so that the set A created contains all the sums of the two other sets created by cutting at x and y. And we have to prove math works on $overline R$. But we can do it. And we do.
But as a consequence we see that every real number is the least upper bound limit of a sequence of rational numbers. That's pretty much the definition of what a "cut point" is; the point that separate all the rationals less than it from all the other rationals.
I like to say (somewhat trivially) that: the real number $x$ is the least upper bound of all the rational numbers that are smaller than $x$. And it's true!
In the real numbers, every real number is the limit of some sequence of rational numbers. And every bounded sequence of rational numbers will have a real number least upper bound limit.
...
Let that sink in for a minute.
=====
Okay, so given a sequence {3, 3.1, 3.14, 3.141,....} = {finite decimals that are less than pi} is a bounded sequence of rational numbers so $pi = $ the limit of the sequence which is also the limit of the infinite sequence 3.1415926....
It now makes sense to talk of $0.9999.... = sum_{i=1}^{infty}9/10^i = lim{sum_{i=1}^n9/10^i}$ = a precise and real number.
And from there we can say with confidence that that number is $1$. (By any of these proofs.)
The problem isn't proving that $0.9999... = 1$. There are many proofs and they all are easy.
The problem is being convinced that every argument you are making actually is valid and makes sense, and not having a sinking feeling you aren't just falling for some parlor trick.
$0.99...9;$ (with $n$ 9s) is $sum_{i= 1}^n frac 9 {10^i}$ so "obviously" $0.999....$ (with an infinite number of 9s) is $sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac 9{10^i}$.
The obvious objection is: does it even make sense to talk about adding an infinite number of terms? How can we talk about taking and adding an infinite number of terms?
And it's a legitimate objection.
So when we learn math in elementary school we are told: Every real number can be written as a decimal expansion (maybe infinite) and every possible decimal expansion is a real number. And this is true. But we are not told why and we are expected to take it on faith, and we usually do.
IF we take this on faith then a proof is very easy:
$0.9999.... = sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac 9{10^i}$
$10*(0.9999....) = 10*sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac 9{10^i}= sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac {90}{10^i}=$
$sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac 9{10^{i-1}} = 9/10^0 + sum_{i = 2}^{infty} frac 9{10^{i-1}}= 9 + sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac 9{10^i}$ (Look at the indexes!)
So...
$10*(0.999...) - (0.9999...) = (10 - 1)*0.9999.... = 9*0.99999.... = $
$9 + sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac 9{10^i} - sum_{i = 1}^{infty} frac 9{10^i} = 9$.
So...
$0.9999.... = 9/9 = 1$.
Easy! !!!!!!!IF!!!!!!! we take it on faith that: Every real number can be written as a decimal expansion (maybe infinite) and every possible decimal expansion is a real number.
So why can we take that on faith? That's the issue: why is that true and what does it mean?
So....
We've got the Integers. We use them to count discrete measurements. We can use an integer to divide a unit 1 into $m$ sub-units to measure measurements of $1/m$. As the $m$ can be as large as we want the $1/m$ can be as precise as we want and the system of all possible $n/m; m ne 0$ can measure any possible quantity with arbitrary and infinite precision.
We hope. We call these $n/m$ numbers the Rationals and everything is fine until we discover that we can't actually measure measurements such as the square root of two or pi.
But the Rationals still have infinite precision. We can get within 1/10 away from pi. We can get within 1/100 away from pi. Within $1/10^n$ for any possible power of 10.
At this point, we hope we can say "we can't measure it with any finite power of 10 but we can always go one more significant measure, so if we go through infinite powers of 10 we will measure it to precision" and we hope that explanation will be convincing.
But it isn't really. We have these "missing numbers" and we can get infinitely close the them, but what are they really?
Well, we decide to become math majors and in our senior year of college we take a Real Analysis course and we find out.
We can view numbers as sets of rational numbers. We can split the rational numbers at any point into two sets. We can split the rational numbers so that all the rational numbers less than 1/2 are in set A and all the rational numbers greater than or equal to 1/2 are in set B (which we ignore; we are only interested in set A.)
These "cuts" can occur at any point but they must follow the following rules:
--the set A of all the smaller rational numbers is not empty. Nor does it contain every rational number. Some rational number is not in it.
--if any rational number (call it q) is in A, then every rational number smaller than q is also in A. (This means that if r is a rational not in A, then every rational bigger than r is also not in A.)
-- A does not have a single largest element. (So it can be all the elements less than 1/2 but it can't be all the elements less than or equal to 1/2).
And we let $overline R$ be the collection of all possible ways to "cut" the rational numbers in half that way.
Notice sometimes the cut will occur at a rational number (all the rationals less than 1/2), but sometimes it will occur at points "between" the rational numbers. (All the rationals whose squares are less than 2). So the collection $overline R$ is a larger set than the set of Rational numbers.
It turns out we can define the Real numbers as the points of $overline R$ where we can cut the rationals in two.
We need to do a bit or work to show that this is actually a number system. We say $x, y in overline R; x < y$ if the "Set A made by cutting at x" $subset$ "Set A made by cutting at y". And we say $x + y = $ the point where we need to cut so that the set A created contains all the sums of the two other sets created by cutting at x and y. And we have to prove math works on $overline R$. But we can do it. And we do.
But as a consequence we see that every real number is the least upper bound limit of a sequence of rational numbers. That's pretty much the definition of what a "cut point" is; the point that separate all the rationals less than it from all the other rationals.
I like to say (somewhat trivially) that: the real number $x$ is the least upper bound of all the rational numbers that are smaller than $x$. And it's true!
In the real numbers, every real number is the limit of some sequence of rational numbers. And every bounded sequence of rational numbers will have a real number least upper bound limit.
...
Let that sink in for a minute.
=====
Okay, so given a sequence {3, 3.1, 3.14, 3.141,....} = {finite decimals that are less than pi} is a bounded sequence of rational numbers so $pi = $ the limit of the sequence which is also the limit of the infinite sequence 3.1415926....
It now makes sense to talk of $0.9999.... = sum_{i=1}^{infty}9/10^i = lim{sum_{i=1}^n9/10^i}$ = a precise and real number.
And from there we can say with confidence that that number is $1$. (By any of these proofs.)
edited Jan 29 '16 at 9:13
community wiki
2 revs, 2 users 99%
fleablood
add a comment |
add a comment |
up vote
6
down vote
Another approach is the following:
$$begin{align}
0.overline9 &=lim_{n to infty} 0.underbrace{99dots 9}_{ntext{ times}} \
&= lim_{n to infty} sumlimits_{k=1}^n frac{9}{10^k} \
&=lim_{n to infty} 1-frac{1}{10^n} \
&=1-lim_{n to infty} frac{1}{10^n} \
&=1.
end{align}$$
7
This approach appears in Isaac's answer from 4 years earlier.
– Jonas Meyer
Aug 26 '14 at 2:15
add a comment |
up vote
6
down vote
Another approach is the following:
$$begin{align}
0.overline9 &=lim_{n to infty} 0.underbrace{99dots 9}_{ntext{ times}} \
&= lim_{n to infty} sumlimits_{k=1}^n frac{9}{10^k} \
&=lim_{n to infty} 1-frac{1}{10^n} \
&=1-lim_{n to infty} frac{1}{10^n} \
&=1.
end{align}$$
7
This approach appears in Isaac's answer from 4 years earlier.
– Jonas Meyer
Aug 26 '14 at 2:15
add a comment |
up vote
6
down vote
up vote
6
down vote
Another approach is the following:
$$begin{align}
0.overline9 &=lim_{n to infty} 0.underbrace{99dots 9}_{ntext{ times}} \
&= lim_{n to infty} sumlimits_{k=1}^n frac{9}{10^k} \
&=lim_{n to infty} 1-frac{1}{10^n} \
&=1-lim_{n to infty} frac{1}{10^n} \
&=1.
end{align}$$
Another approach is the following:
$$begin{align}
0.overline9 &=lim_{n to infty} 0.underbrace{99dots 9}_{ntext{ times}} \
&= lim_{n to infty} sumlimits_{k=1}^n frac{9}{10^k} \
&=lim_{n to infty} 1-frac{1}{10^n} \
&=1-lim_{n to infty} frac{1}{10^n} \
&=1.
end{align}$$
edited Dec 11 at 11:30
community wiki
2 revs, 2 users 54%
Shaun
7
This approach appears in Isaac's answer from 4 years earlier.
– Jonas Meyer
Aug 26 '14 at 2:15
add a comment |
7
This approach appears in Isaac's answer from 4 years earlier.
– Jonas Meyer
Aug 26 '14 at 2:15
7
7
This approach appears in Isaac's answer from 4 years earlier.
– Jonas Meyer
Aug 26 '14 at 2:15
This approach appears in Isaac's answer from 4 years earlier.
– Jonas Meyer
Aug 26 '14 at 2:15
add a comment |
up vote
5
down vote
There are some situations in which something like $0.99999ldots < 1$ indeed holds. Here is one coming from social choice theory.
Let $w_1>w_2>ldots$ be an infinite sequence of positive numbers, and let $T$ be a number in the range $(0,sum_i w_i)$. Pick an index $i$. Choose a random permutation $pi$ of the positive integers, and consider the running totals
$$
w_{pi(1)}, w_{pi(1)} + w_{pi(2)}, w_{pi(1)} + w_{pi(2)} + w_{pi(3)}, cdots
$$
The Shapley value $varphi_i(T)$ is the probability that the first time that the running total exceeds $T$ is when $w_i$ is added.
We will particularly be interested in the case in which the sequence $w_i$ is super-increasing: for each $i$, $w_i geq sum_{j=i+1}^infty w_j$. The simplest case is $w_i = 2^{-i}$. Every number $T in (0,1)$ can be written in the form
$$ T = 2^{-a_0} + 2^{-a_1} + cdots, qquad a_0 < a_1 < cdots. $$
In this case we can give an explicit formula for $varphi_i(T)$:
$$
varphi_i(T) = begin{cases}
sum_{tcolon a_t>i} frac{1}{a_t binom{a_t-1}{t}} & text{if } i notin {a_0,a_1,ldots}, \
frac{1}{a_s binom{a_s-1}{s}} - sum_{tcolon a_t>i} frac{1}{a_t binom{a_t-1}{t-1}} & text{if } i = a_s.
end{cases}
$$
The first two functions are plotted here:
What happens for different sets of weights? The same formula applies, for
$$
T = w_{a_0} + w_{a_1} + cdots, qquad a_0 < a_1 < cdots.
$$
In general not all $T$ will be of this form; for $T$ not of this form, we take the lowest upper bound which is of this form. What we get for $w_i = 3^{-i}$ is:
Notice all the horizontal parts, for example the blue line at $y=1$ at $x in (1/6,1/3)$. Where does this stem from? Note that $1/3 = 3^{-1} = w_1$, whereas $1/6 = sum_{i=2}^infty 3^{-i} = sum_{i=2}^infty w_i$. If we substitute $w_i = 2^{-i}$, then $1/3$ corresponds to $0.1$ (in binary), whereas $1/6$ corresponds to $0.011111ldots$. So in this case there is a (visible) gap between $0.011111ldots$ and $0.1$!
For more, take a look at this question and this manuscript.
add a comment |
up vote
5
down vote
There are some situations in which something like $0.99999ldots < 1$ indeed holds. Here is one coming from social choice theory.
Let $w_1>w_2>ldots$ be an infinite sequence of positive numbers, and let $T$ be a number in the range $(0,sum_i w_i)$. Pick an index $i$. Choose a random permutation $pi$ of the positive integers, and consider the running totals
$$
w_{pi(1)}, w_{pi(1)} + w_{pi(2)}, w_{pi(1)} + w_{pi(2)} + w_{pi(3)}, cdots
$$
The Shapley value $varphi_i(T)$ is the probability that the first time that the running total exceeds $T$ is when $w_i$ is added.
We will particularly be interested in the case in which the sequence $w_i$ is super-increasing: for each $i$, $w_i geq sum_{j=i+1}^infty w_j$. The simplest case is $w_i = 2^{-i}$. Every number $T in (0,1)$ can be written in the form
$$ T = 2^{-a_0} + 2^{-a_1} + cdots, qquad a_0 < a_1 < cdots. $$
In this case we can give an explicit formula for $varphi_i(T)$:
$$
varphi_i(T) = begin{cases}
sum_{tcolon a_t>i} frac{1}{a_t binom{a_t-1}{t}} & text{if } i notin {a_0,a_1,ldots}, \
frac{1}{a_s binom{a_s-1}{s}} - sum_{tcolon a_t>i} frac{1}{a_t binom{a_t-1}{t-1}} & text{if } i = a_s.
end{cases}
$$
The first two functions are plotted here:
What happens for different sets of weights? The same formula applies, for
$$
T = w_{a_0} + w_{a_1} + cdots, qquad a_0 < a_1 < cdots.
$$
In general not all $T$ will be of this form; for $T$ not of this form, we take the lowest upper bound which is of this form. What we get for $w_i = 3^{-i}$ is:
Notice all the horizontal parts, for example the blue line at $y=1$ at $x in (1/6,1/3)$. Where does this stem from? Note that $1/3 = 3^{-1} = w_1$, whereas $1/6 = sum_{i=2}^infty 3^{-i} = sum_{i=2}^infty w_i$. If we substitute $w_i = 2^{-i}$, then $1/3$ corresponds to $0.1$ (in binary), whereas $1/6$ corresponds to $0.011111ldots$. So in this case there is a (visible) gap between $0.011111ldots$ and $0.1$!
For more, take a look at this question and this manuscript.
add a comment |
up vote
5
down vote
up vote
5
down vote
There are some situations in which something like $0.99999ldots < 1$ indeed holds. Here is one coming from social choice theory.
Let $w_1>w_2>ldots$ be an infinite sequence of positive numbers, and let $T$ be a number in the range $(0,sum_i w_i)$. Pick an index $i$. Choose a random permutation $pi$ of the positive integers, and consider the running totals
$$
w_{pi(1)}, w_{pi(1)} + w_{pi(2)}, w_{pi(1)} + w_{pi(2)} + w_{pi(3)}, cdots
$$
The Shapley value $varphi_i(T)$ is the probability that the first time that the running total exceeds $T$ is when $w_i$ is added.
We will particularly be interested in the case in which the sequence $w_i$ is super-increasing: for each $i$, $w_i geq sum_{j=i+1}^infty w_j$. The simplest case is $w_i = 2^{-i}$. Every number $T in (0,1)$ can be written in the form
$$ T = 2^{-a_0} + 2^{-a_1} + cdots, qquad a_0 < a_1 < cdots. $$
In this case we can give an explicit formula for $varphi_i(T)$:
$$
varphi_i(T) = begin{cases}
sum_{tcolon a_t>i} frac{1}{a_t binom{a_t-1}{t}} & text{if } i notin {a_0,a_1,ldots}, \
frac{1}{a_s binom{a_s-1}{s}} - sum_{tcolon a_t>i} frac{1}{a_t binom{a_t-1}{t-1}} & text{if } i = a_s.
end{cases}
$$
The first two functions are plotted here:
What happens for different sets of weights? The same formula applies, for
$$
T = w_{a_0} + w_{a_1} + cdots, qquad a_0 < a_1 < cdots.
$$
In general not all $T$ will be of this form; for $T$ not of this form, we take the lowest upper bound which is of this form. What we get for $w_i = 3^{-i}$ is:
Notice all the horizontal parts, for example the blue line at $y=1$ at $x in (1/6,1/3)$. Where does this stem from? Note that $1/3 = 3^{-1} = w_1$, whereas $1/6 = sum_{i=2}^infty 3^{-i} = sum_{i=2}^infty w_i$. If we substitute $w_i = 2^{-i}$, then $1/3$ corresponds to $0.1$ (in binary), whereas $1/6$ corresponds to $0.011111ldots$. So in this case there is a (visible) gap between $0.011111ldots$ and $0.1$!
For more, take a look at this question and this manuscript.
There are some situations in which something like $0.99999ldots < 1$ indeed holds. Here is one coming from social choice theory.
Let $w_1>w_2>ldots$ be an infinite sequence of positive numbers, and let $T$ be a number in the range $(0,sum_i w_i)$. Pick an index $i$. Choose a random permutation $pi$ of the positive integers, and consider the running totals
$$
w_{pi(1)}, w_{pi(1)} + w_{pi(2)}, w_{pi(1)} + w_{pi(2)} + w_{pi(3)}, cdots
$$
The Shapley value $varphi_i(T)$ is the probability that the first time that the running total exceeds $T$ is when $w_i$ is added.
We will particularly be interested in the case in which the sequence $w_i$ is super-increasing: for each $i$, $w_i geq sum_{j=i+1}^infty w_j$. The simplest case is $w_i = 2^{-i}$. Every number $T in (0,1)$ can be written in the form
$$ T = 2^{-a_0} + 2^{-a_1} + cdots, qquad a_0 < a_1 < cdots. $$
In this case we can give an explicit formula for $varphi_i(T)$:
$$
varphi_i(T) = begin{cases}
sum_{tcolon a_t>i} frac{1}{a_t binom{a_t-1}{t}} & text{if } i notin {a_0,a_1,ldots}, \
frac{1}{a_s binom{a_s-1}{s}} - sum_{tcolon a_t>i} frac{1}{a_t binom{a_t-1}{t-1}} & text{if } i = a_s.
end{cases}
$$
The first two functions are plotted here:
What happens for different sets of weights? The same formula applies, for
$$
T = w_{a_0} + w_{a_1} + cdots, qquad a_0 < a_1 < cdots.
$$
In general not all $T$ will be of this form; for $T$ not of this form, we take the lowest upper bound which is of this form. What we get for $w_i = 3^{-i}$ is:
Notice all the horizontal parts, for example the blue line at $y=1$ at $x in (1/6,1/3)$. Where does this stem from? Note that $1/3 = 3^{-1} = w_1$, whereas $1/6 = sum_{i=2}^infty 3^{-i} = sum_{i=2}^infty w_i$. If we substitute $w_i = 2^{-i}$, then $1/3$ corresponds to $0.1$ (in binary), whereas $1/6$ corresponds to $0.011111ldots$. So in this case there is a (visible) gap between $0.011111ldots$ and $0.1$!
For more, take a look at this question and this manuscript.
edited Apr 13 '17 at 12:19
community wiki
2 revs
Yuval Filmus
add a comment |
add a comment |
up vote
4
down vote
One cool way I learned to prove this is that, assuming by $0.99999...$ you mean $0.bar{9}$. Well we can say that
$$0.bar{9}=sum_{n=1}^{infty}9cdot 10^{-n}=9sum_{n=1}^{infty}frac{1}{10^n}$$
Which we know converges by fact that this is a geometric series with the ratio between terms being less than $1$. So we know that
$$9sum_{n=1}^{infty}frac{1}{10^n}=9left(frac{1}{1-frac{1}{10}}-1right)=10-9=1$$
Note that we subtract off the $1$ in the parentheses because we started indexing at $1$ rather than at $0$, so we have to subtract of the value of the sequence at $n=0$ which is $1$.
2
"Which we know converges by fact that this is a geometric series with the ratio between terms being less than 1." I don't think anyone who does know this would be questioning whether .9999.... = 1. The only people who are confused on the concept most assuredly do not know this.
– fleablood
Jan 15 '16 at 20:03
Just because you have studied series doesn't mean you have seen this proof. Hence why I have added it as a wiki answer on such a highly up voted answer, which people visiting it do not necessary have the same mathematical knowledge as the OP.
– Will Fisher
Jan 15 '16 at 21:55
add a comment |
up vote
4
down vote
One cool way I learned to prove this is that, assuming by $0.99999...$ you mean $0.bar{9}$. Well we can say that
$$0.bar{9}=sum_{n=1}^{infty}9cdot 10^{-n}=9sum_{n=1}^{infty}frac{1}{10^n}$$
Which we know converges by fact that this is a geometric series with the ratio between terms being less than $1$. So we know that
$$9sum_{n=1}^{infty}frac{1}{10^n}=9left(frac{1}{1-frac{1}{10}}-1right)=10-9=1$$
Note that we subtract off the $1$ in the parentheses because we started indexing at $1$ rather than at $0$, so we have to subtract of the value of the sequence at $n=0$ which is $1$.
2
"Which we know converges by fact that this is a geometric series with the ratio between terms being less than 1." I don't think anyone who does know this would be questioning whether .9999.... = 1. The only people who are confused on the concept most assuredly do not know this.
– fleablood
Jan 15 '16 at 20:03
Just because you have studied series doesn't mean you have seen this proof. Hence why I have added it as a wiki answer on such a highly up voted answer, which people visiting it do not necessary have the same mathematical knowledge as the OP.
– Will Fisher
Jan 15 '16 at 21:55
add a comment |
up vote
4
down vote
up vote
4
down vote
One cool way I learned to prove this is that, assuming by $0.99999...$ you mean $0.bar{9}$. Well we can say that
$$0.bar{9}=sum_{n=1}^{infty}9cdot 10^{-n}=9sum_{n=1}^{infty}frac{1}{10^n}$$
Which we know converges by fact that this is a geometric series with the ratio between terms being less than $1$. So we know that
$$9sum_{n=1}^{infty}frac{1}{10^n}=9left(frac{1}{1-frac{1}{10}}-1right)=10-9=1$$
Note that we subtract off the $1$ in the parentheses because we started indexing at $1$ rather than at $0$, so we have to subtract of the value of the sequence at $n=0$ which is $1$.
One cool way I learned to prove this is that, assuming by $0.99999...$ you mean $0.bar{9}$. Well we can say that
$$0.bar{9}=sum_{n=1}^{infty}9cdot 10^{-n}=9sum_{n=1}^{infty}frac{1}{10^n}$$
Which we know converges by fact that this is a geometric series with the ratio between terms being less than $1$. So we know that
$$9sum_{n=1}^{infty}frac{1}{10^n}=9left(frac{1}{1-frac{1}{10}}-1right)=10-9=1$$
Note that we subtract off the $1$ in the parentheses because we started indexing at $1$ rather than at $0$, so we have to subtract of the value of the sequence at $n=0$ which is $1$.
answered Dec 28 '15 at 22:45
community wiki
Will Fisher
2
"Which we know converges by fact that this is a geometric series with the ratio between terms being less than 1." I don't think anyone who does know this would be questioning whether .9999.... = 1. The only people who are confused on the concept most assuredly do not know this.
– fleablood
Jan 15 '16 at 20:03
Just because you have studied series doesn't mean you have seen this proof. Hence why I have added it as a wiki answer on such a highly up voted answer, which people visiting it do not necessary have the same mathematical knowledge as the OP.
– Will Fisher
Jan 15 '16 at 21:55
add a comment |
2
"Which we know converges by fact that this is a geometric series with the ratio between terms being less than 1." I don't think anyone who does know this would be questioning whether .9999.... = 1. The only people who are confused on the concept most assuredly do not know this.
– fleablood
Jan 15 '16 at 20:03
Just because you have studied series doesn't mean you have seen this proof. Hence why I have added it as a wiki answer on such a highly up voted answer, which people visiting it do not necessary have the same mathematical knowledge as the OP.
– Will Fisher
Jan 15 '16 at 21:55
2
2
"Which we know converges by fact that this is a geometric series with the ratio between terms being less than 1." I don't think anyone who does know this would be questioning whether .9999.... = 1. The only people who are confused on the concept most assuredly do not know this.
– fleablood
Jan 15 '16 at 20:03
"Which we know converges by fact that this is a geometric series with the ratio between terms being less than 1." I don't think anyone who does know this would be questioning whether .9999.... = 1. The only people who are confused on the concept most assuredly do not know this.
– fleablood
Jan 15 '16 at 20:03
Just because you have studied series doesn't mean you have seen this proof. Hence why I have added it as a wiki answer on such a highly up voted answer, which people visiting it do not necessary have the same mathematical knowledge as the OP.
– Will Fisher
Jan 15 '16 at 21:55
Just because you have studied series doesn't mean you have seen this proof. Hence why I have added it as a wiki answer on such a highly up voted answer, which people visiting it do not necessary have the same mathematical knowledge as the OP.
– Will Fisher
Jan 15 '16 at 21:55
add a comment |
up vote
3
down vote
Here's my favorite reason why $.999ldots$ should equal $1$:$^{*}$
begin{align*}
.999ldots + .999ldots
&= (.9 + .09 + .009 + cdots) + (.9 + .09 + .009 + cdots) \
&= (.9 + .9) + (.09 + .09) + (.009 + .009) + cdots \
&= 1.8 + .18 + .018 + .0018 + cdots \
&= (1 + .8) + (.1 + .08) + (.01 + .008) + (.001 + .0008) + cdots \
&= 1 + (.8 + .1) + (.08 + .01) + (.008 + .001) + cdots \
&= 1 + .9 + .09 + .009 + cdots \
&= 1 + .999ldots
end{align*}
It follows subtracting $.999ldots$ from both sides that $.999ldots = 1$.
The reason I like this explanation best is that addition of (positive) infinite decimal expansions (defined in a particular way) is both commutative and associative even if you insist that $.999ldots$ and $1$ are different numbers. That is, it forms a commutative monoid.
But the cancellation property fails: if $a + b = a + c$, then we can't necessarily conclude $b = c$. The example of this is above, and the most fundamental reason why $.999ldots = 1$ is arguably so that the cancellation property can hold.
$^{*}$The calculation given here (using rearrangmenet and regrouping of terms) is informal, and not intended to be a proof, but rather to give some idea of how you can add infinite decimal expansions in the monoid where $.999ldots ne 1$. It does end up being true that $.999ldots + .999ldots = 1 + .999ldots$ in this monoid.
2
It doesn't feel convincing to me to assume that blithely that you can rearrange the infinite sums the way you do here, without changing their value. It is true that it is safe in this particular case, but I don't see how one can show that except by developing enough of a theory of limits that we might as well just sum $sum_{n=1}^infty 9/10^n$ directly.
– Henning Makholm
Jul 17 '16 at 2:46
@HenningMakholm Right--it's not a convincing proof that $.999ldots = 1$ unless you accept that infinite sums of real numbers can be rearranged and regrouped in any way (which is true of course but much more nontrivial than the basic result that the limit of $.999ldots$ is $1$).
– 6005
Jul 17 '16 at 4:19
My actual point is that you can define the addition of infinite expansions even while you insist that $.999ldots ne 1$, and if you do so (although I don't give the definition) you get $.999ldots + .999ldots = 1 + .999ldots$. The aligned equation is just informal rearrangements but is intended to sort of show how the definition of addition of infinite decimal expansions would work, in this case at least.
– 6005
Jul 17 '16 at 4:20
1
It is not true in general that "infinite sums of real numbers can be rearranged and regrouped in any way". It works in this particular case because all of the terms being rearranged are all positive -- but in order to argue that this is safer than the general case (rearranging a conditionally convergent series such as $sum frac{(-1)^n}{n}$ fails spectacularly) it seems that you need to develop so much material that you cannot really keep open an option for $0.999...$ to differ from $1$.
– Henning Makholm
Jul 17 '16 at 9:12
@HenningMakholm Oh I'm sorry, that was a typo. Of course I'm aware. I meant positive real numbers.
– 6005
Jul 17 '16 at 14:43
|
show 1 more comment
up vote
3
down vote
Here's my favorite reason why $.999ldots$ should equal $1$:$^{*}$
begin{align*}
.999ldots + .999ldots
&= (.9 + .09 + .009 + cdots) + (.9 + .09 + .009 + cdots) \
&= (.9 + .9) + (.09 + .09) + (.009 + .009) + cdots \
&= 1.8 + .18 + .018 + .0018 + cdots \
&= (1 + .8) + (.1 + .08) + (.01 + .008) + (.001 + .0008) + cdots \
&= 1 + (.8 + .1) + (.08 + .01) + (.008 + .001) + cdots \
&= 1 + .9 + .09 + .009 + cdots \
&= 1 + .999ldots
end{align*}
It follows subtracting $.999ldots$ from both sides that $.999ldots = 1$.
The reason I like this explanation best is that addition of (positive) infinite decimal expansions (defined in a particular way) is both commutative and associative even if you insist that $.999ldots$ and $1$ are different numbers. That is, it forms a commutative monoid.
But the cancellation property fails: if $a + b = a + c$, then we can't necessarily conclude $b = c$. The example of this is above, and the most fundamental reason why $.999ldots = 1$ is arguably so that the cancellation property can hold.
$^{*}$The calculation given here (using rearrangmenet and regrouping of terms) is informal, and not intended to be a proof, but rather to give some idea of how you can add infinite decimal expansions in the monoid where $.999ldots ne 1$. It does end up being true that $.999ldots + .999ldots = 1 + .999ldots$ in this monoid.
2
It doesn't feel convincing to me to assume that blithely that you can rearrange the infinite sums the way you do here, without changing their value. It is true that it is safe in this particular case, but I don't see how one can show that except by developing enough of a theory of limits that we might as well just sum $sum_{n=1}^infty 9/10^n$ directly.
– Henning Makholm
Jul 17 '16 at 2:46
@HenningMakholm Right--it's not a convincing proof that $.999ldots = 1$ unless you accept that infinite sums of real numbers can be rearranged and regrouped in any way (which is true of course but much more nontrivial than the basic result that the limit of $.999ldots$ is $1$).
– 6005
Jul 17 '16 at 4:19
My actual point is that you can define the addition of infinite expansions even while you insist that $.999ldots ne 1$, and if you do so (although I don't give the definition) you get $.999ldots + .999ldots = 1 + .999ldots$. The aligned equation is just informal rearrangements but is intended to sort of show how the definition of addition of infinite decimal expansions would work, in this case at least.
– 6005
Jul 17 '16 at 4:20
1
It is not true in general that "infinite sums of real numbers can be rearranged and regrouped in any way". It works in this particular case because all of the terms being rearranged are all positive -- but in order to argue that this is safer than the general case (rearranging a conditionally convergent series such as $sum frac{(-1)^n}{n}$ fails spectacularly) it seems that you need to develop so much material that you cannot really keep open an option for $0.999...$ to differ from $1$.
– Henning Makholm
Jul 17 '16 at 9:12
@HenningMakholm Oh I'm sorry, that was a typo. Of course I'm aware. I meant positive real numbers.
– 6005
Jul 17 '16 at 14:43
|
show 1 more comment
up vote
3
down vote
up vote
3
down vote
Here's my favorite reason why $.999ldots$ should equal $1$:$^{*}$
begin{align*}
.999ldots + .999ldots
&= (.9 + .09 + .009 + cdots) + (.9 + .09 + .009 + cdots) \
&= (.9 + .9) + (.09 + .09) + (.009 + .009) + cdots \
&= 1.8 + .18 + .018 + .0018 + cdots \
&= (1 + .8) + (.1 + .08) + (.01 + .008) + (.001 + .0008) + cdots \
&= 1 + (.8 + .1) + (.08 + .01) + (.008 + .001) + cdots \
&= 1 + .9 + .09 + .009 + cdots \
&= 1 + .999ldots
end{align*}
It follows subtracting $.999ldots$ from both sides that $.999ldots = 1$.
The reason I like this explanation best is that addition of (positive) infinite decimal expansions (defined in a particular way) is both commutative and associative even if you insist that $.999ldots$ and $1$ are different numbers. That is, it forms a commutative monoid.
But the cancellation property fails: if $a + b = a + c$, then we can't necessarily conclude $b = c$. The example of this is above, and the most fundamental reason why $.999ldots = 1$ is arguably so that the cancellation property can hold.
$^{*}$The calculation given here (using rearrangmenet and regrouping of terms) is informal, and not intended to be a proof, but rather to give some idea of how you can add infinite decimal expansions in the monoid where $.999ldots ne 1$. It does end up being true that $.999ldots + .999ldots = 1 + .999ldots$ in this monoid.
Here's my favorite reason why $.999ldots$ should equal $1$:$^{*}$
begin{align*}
.999ldots + .999ldots
&= (.9 + .09 + .009 + cdots) + (.9 + .09 + .009 + cdots) \
&= (.9 + .9) + (.09 + .09) + (.009 + .009) + cdots \
&= 1.8 + .18 + .018 + .0018 + cdots \
&= (1 + .8) + (.1 + .08) + (.01 + .008) + (.001 + .0008) + cdots \
&= 1 + (.8 + .1) + (.08 + .01) + (.008 + .001) + cdots \
&= 1 + .9 + .09 + .009 + cdots \
&= 1 + .999ldots
end{align*}
It follows subtracting $.999ldots$ from both sides that $.999ldots = 1$.
The reason I like this explanation best is that addition of (positive) infinite decimal expansions (defined in a particular way) is both commutative and associative even if you insist that $.999ldots$ and $1$ are different numbers. That is, it forms a commutative monoid.
But the cancellation property fails: if $a + b = a + c$, then we can't necessarily conclude $b = c$. The example of this is above, and the most fundamental reason why $.999ldots = 1$ is arguably so that the cancellation property can hold.
$^{*}$The calculation given here (using rearrangmenet and regrouping of terms) is informal, and not intended to be a proof, but rather to give some idea of how you can add infinite decimal expansions in the monoid where $.999ldots ne 1$. It does end up being true that $.999ldots + .999ldots = 1 + .999ldots$ in this monoid.
edited Aug 4 '16 at 13:18
community wiki
3 revs
6005
2
It doesn't feel convincing to me to assume that blithely that you can rearrange the infinite sums the way you do here, without changing their value. It is true that it is safe in this particular case, but I don't see how one can show that except by developing enough of a theory of limits that we might as well just sum $sum_{n=1}^infty 9/10^n$ directly.
– Henning Makholm
Jul 17 '16 at 2:46
@HenningMakholm Right--it's not a convincing proof that $.999ldots = 1$ unless you accept that infinite sums of real numbers can be rearranged and regrouped in any way (which is true of course but much more nontrivial than the basic result that the limit of $.999ldots$ is $1$).
– 6005
Jul 17 '16 at 4:19
My actual point is that you can define the addition of infinite expansions even while you insist that $.999ldots ne 1$, and if you do so (although I don't give the definition) you get $.999ldots + .999ldots = 1 + .999ldots$. The aligned equation is just informal rearrangements but is intended to sort of show how the definition of addition of infinite decimal expansions would work, in this case at least.
– 6005
Jul 17 '16 at 4:20
1
It is not true in general that "infinite sums of real numbers can be rearranged and regrouped in any way". It works in this particular case because all of the terms being rearranged are all positive -- but in order to argue that this is safer than the general case (rearranging a conditionally convergent series such as $sum frac{(-1)^n}{n}$ fails spectacularly) it seems that you need to develop so much material that you cannot really keep open an option for $0.999...$ to differ from $1$.
– Henning Makholm
Jul 17 '16 at 9:12
@HenningMakholm Oh I'm sorry, that was a typo. Of course I'm aware. I meant positive real numbers.
– 6005
Jul 17 '16 at 14:43
|
show 1 more comment
2
It doesn't feel convincing to me to assume that blithely that you can rearrange the infinite sums the way you do here, without changing their value. It is true that it is safe in this particular case, but I don't see how one can show that except by developing enough of a theory of limits that we might as well just sum $sum_{n=1}^infty 9/10^n$ directly.
– Henning Makholm
Jul 17 '16 at 2:46
@HenningMakholm Right--it's not a convincing proof that $.999ldots = 1$ unless you accept that infinite sums of real numbers can be rearranged and regrouped in any way (which is true of course but much more nontrivial than the basic result that the limit of $.999ldots$ is $1$).
– 6005
Jul 17 '16 at 4:19
My actual point is that you can define the addition of infinite expansions even while you insist that $.999ldots ne 1$, and if you do so (although I don't give the definition) you get $.999ldots + .999ldots = 1 + .999ldots$. The aligned equation is just informal rearrangements but is intended to sort of show how the definition of addition of infinite decimal expansions would work, in this case at least.
– 6005
Jul 17 '16 at 4:20
1
It is not true in general that "infinite sums of real numbers can be rearranged and regrouped in any way". It works in this particular case because all of the terms being rearranged are all positive -- but in order to argue that this is safer than the general case (rearranging a conditionally convergent series such as $sum frac{(-1)^n}{n}$ fails spectacularly) it seems that you need to develop so much material that you cannot really keep open an option for $0.999...$ to differ from $1$.
– Henning Makholm
Jul 17 '16 at 9:12
@HenningMakholm Oh I'm sorry, that was a typo. Of course I'm aware. I meant positive real numbers.
– 6005
Jul 17 '16 at 14:43
2
2
It doesn't feel convincing to me to assume that blithely that you can rearrange the infinite sums the way you do here, without changing their value. It is true that it is safe in this particular case, but I don't see how one can show that except by developing enough of a theory of limits that we might as well just sum $sum_{n=1}^infty 9/10^n$ directly.
– Henning Makholm
Jul 17 '16 at 2:46
It doesn't feel convincing to me to assume that blithely that you can rearrange the infinite sums the way you do here, without changing their value. It is true that it is safe in this particular case, but I don't see how one can show that except by developing enough of a theory of limits that we might as well just sum $sum_{n=1}^infty 9/10^n$ directly.
– Henning Makholm
Jul 17 '16 at 2:46
@HenningMakholm Right--it's not a convincing proof that $.999ldots = 1$ unless you accept that infinite sums of real numbers can be rearranged and regrouped in any way (which is true of course but much more nontrivial than the basic result that the limit of $.999ldots$ is $1$).
– 6005
Jul 17 '16 at 4:19
@HenningMakholm Right--it's not a convincing proof that $.999ldots = 1$ unless you accept that infinite sums of real numbers can be rearranged and regrouped in any way (which is true of course but much more nontrivial than the basic result that the limit of $.999ldots$ is $1$).
– 6005
Jul 17 '16 at 4:19
My actual point is that you can define the addition of infinite expansions even while you insist that $.999ldots ne 1$, and if you do so (although I don't give the definition) you get $.999ldots + .999ldots = 1 + .999ldots$. The aligned equation is just informal rearrangements but is intended to sort of show how the definition of addition of infinite decimal expansions would work, in this case at least.
– 6005
Jul 17 '16 at 4:20
My actual point is that you can define the addition of infinite expansions even while you insist that $.999ldots ne 1$, and if you do so (although I don't give the definition) you get $.999ldots + .999ldots = 1 + .999ldots$. The aligned equation is just informal rearrangements but is intended to sort of show how the definition of addition of infinite decimal expansions would work, in this case at least.
– 6005
Jul 17 '16 at 4:20
1
1
It is not true in general that "infinite sums of real numbers can be rearranged and regrouped in any way". It works in this particular case because all of the terms being rearranged are all positive -- but in order to argue that this is safer than the general case (rearranging a conditionally convergent series such as $sum frac{(-1)^n}{n}$ fails spectacularly) it seems that you need to develop so much material that you cannot really keep open an option for $0.999...$ to differ from $1$.
– Henning Makholm
Jul 17 '16 at 9:12
It is not true in general that "infinite sums of real numbers can be rearranged and regrouped in any way". It works in this particular case because all of the terms being rearranged are all positive -- but in order to argue that this is safer than the general case (rearranging a conditionally convergent series such as $sum frac{(-1)^n}{n}$ fails spectacularly) it seems that you need to develop so much material that you cannot really keep open an option for $0.999...$ to differ from $1$.
– Henning Makholm
Jul 17 '16 at 9:12
@HenningMakholm Oh I'm sorry, that was a typo. Of course I'm aware. I meant positive real numbers.
– 6005
Jul 17 '16 at 14:43
@HenningMakholm Oh I'm sorry, that was a typo. Of course I'm aware. I meant positive real numbers.
– 6005
Jul 17 '16 at 14:43
|
show 1 more comment
up vote
3
down vote
Use the Squeeze Theorem:
$$0<1-0.999...=0.1+0.9-0.999...=0.1-0.0999...<0.1=0.1^1$$
$$0<0.1-0.0999...=0.01+0.09-0.0999...=0.01-0.00999...<0.01=0.1^2$$
$$...$$
$$0<1-0.999...<0.1^n$$
$$0le 1-0.999... le limlimits_{ntoinfty}0.1^n=0.$$
add a comment |
up vote
3
down vote
Use the Squeeze Theorem:
$$0<1-0.999...=0.1+0.9-0.999...=0.1-0.0999...<0.1=0.1^1$$
$$0<0.1-0.0999...=0.01+0.09-0.0999...=0.01-0.00999...<0.01=0.1^2$$
$$...$$
$$0<1-0.999...<0.1^n$$
$$0le 1-0.999... le limlimits_{ntoinfty}0.1^n=0.$$
add a comment |
up vote
3
down vote
up vote
3
down vote
Use the Squeeze Theorem:
$$0<1-0.999...=0.1+0.9-0.999...=0.1-0.0999...<0.1=0.1^1$$
$$0<0.1-0.0999...=0.01+0.09-0.0999...=0.01-0.00999...<0.01=0.1^2$$
$$...$$
$$0<1-0.999...<0.1^n$$
$$0le 1-0.999... le limlimits_{ntoinfty}0.1^n=0.$$
Use the Squeeze Theorem:
$$0<1-0.999...=0.1+0.9-0.999...=0.1-0.0999...<0.1=0.1^1$$
$$0<0.1-0.0999...=0.01+0.09-0.0999...=0.01-0.00999...<0.01=0.1^2$$
$$...$$
$$0<1-0.999...<0.1^n$$
$$0le 1-0.999... le limlimits_{ntoinfty}0.1^n=0.$$
answered May 25 '17 at 12:28
community wiki
farruhota
add a comment |
add a comment |
up vote
1
down vote
If we take a version of decimal notation with full complement it is indeed so.
In this system, instead of allowing $0.2$ and $0.1999...$ we restrict decimal notation to use only infinite version $0.19999...$ shortly written as $0.1overline{9}$
Simply, we do not allow an infinite trail of zeros.
In this system, there is no $0$ written as $0.000...$ instead it is $...999.999...$ or with our succinct notation $overline{9}.overline{9}$
Negative numbers are written in complement notation. For example, $...998.999...=overline{9}8.overline{9}=-1$
All rules of multiplication addition subtraction are totally valid.
In this system, it is indeed $0.99999...=0.overline{9}=1$ because we cannot represent $1$ as $1.0000...$.
add a comment |
up vote
1
down vote
If we take a version of decimal notation with full complement it is indeed so.
In this system, instead of allowing $0.2$ and $0.1999...$ we restrict decimal notation to use only infinite version $0.19999...$ shortly written as $0.1overline{9}$
Simply, we do not allow an infinite trail of zeros.
In this system, there is no $0$ written as $0.000...$ instead it is $...999.999...$ or with our succinct notation $overline{9}.overline{9}$
Negative numbers are written in complement notation. For example, $...998.999...=overline{9}8.overline{9}=-1$
All rules of multiplication addition subtraction are totally valid.
In this system, it is indeed $0.99999...=0.overline{9}=1$ because we cannot represent $1$ as $1.0000...$.
add a comment |
up vote
1
down vote
up vote
1
down vote
If we take a version of decimal notation with full complement it is indeed so.
In this system, instead of allowing $0.2$ and $0.1999...$ we restrict decimal notation to use only infinite version $0.19999...$ shortly written as $0.1overline{9}$
Simply, we do not allow an infinite trail of zeros.
In this system, there is no $0$ written as $0.000...$ instead it is $...999.999...$ or with our succinct notation $overline{9}.overline{9}$
Negative numbers are written in complement notation. For example, $...998.999...=overline{9}8.overline{9}=-1$
All rules of multiplication addition subtraction are totally valid.
In this system, it is indeed $0.99999...=0.overline{9}=1$ because we cannot represent $1$ as $1.0000...$.
If we take a version of decimal notation with full complement it is indeed so.
In this system, instead of allowing $0.2$ and $0.1999...$ we restrict decimal notation to use only infinite version $0.19999...$ shortly written as $0.1overline{9}$
Simply, we do not allow an infinite trail of zeros.
In this system, there is no $0$ written as $0.000...$ instead it is $...999.999...$ or with our succinct notation $overline{9}.overline{9}$
Negative numbers are written in complement notation. For example, $...998.999...=overline{9}8.overline{9}=-1$
All rules of multiplication addition subtraction are totally valid.
In this system, it is indeed $0.99999...=0.overline{9}=1$ because we cannot represent $1$ as $1.0000...$.
edited Apr 10 at 21:13
community wiki
11 revs
user318107
add a comment |
add a comment |
up vote
0
down vote
The direct proof:
$$0.9999999999...=lim_{ntoinfty} left( 1-frac {1}{10^n}right)=1-0=1$$
Q.E.D.
add a comment |
up vote
0
down vote
The direct proof:
$$0.9999999999...=lim_{ntoinfty} left( 1-frac {1}{10^n}right)=1-0=1$$
Q.E.D.
add a comment |
up vote
0
down vote
up vote
0
down vote
The direct proof:
$$0.9999999999...=lim_{ntoinfty} left( 1-frac {1}{10^n}right)=1-0=1$$
Q.E.D.
The direct proof:
$$0.9999999999...=lim_{ntoinfty} left( 1-frac {1}{10^n}right)=1-0=1$$
Q.E.D.
answered Sep 4 at 9:22
community wiki
Math
add a comment |
add a comment |
up vote
0
down vote
If you allow a "decimal representation" of a number to end finally with period $9$ as in $0.bar9$ or $1.123bar9$ this "decimal representation "of a number would not be unique.
We know by definition that $0.bar9=sum_{n=1}^{infty}(9/10)^n=1$, but for the sake of the uniquenes of the decimal representation $0.bar9$ is not a decimal representation of any number.
add a comment |
up vote
0
down vote
If you allow a "decimal representation" of a number to end finally with period $9$ as in $0.bar9$ or $1.123bar9$ this "decimal representation "of a number would not be unique.
We know by definition that $0.bar9=sum_{n=1}^{infty}(9/10)^n=1$, but for the sake of the uniquenes of the decimal representation $0.bar9$ is not a decimal representation of any number.
add a comment |
up vote
0
down vote
up vote
0
down vote
If you allow a "decimal representation" of a number to end finally with period $9$ as in $0.bar9$ or $1.123bar9$ this "decimal representation "of a number would not be unique.
We know by definition that $0.bar9=sum_{n=1}^{infty}(9/10)^n=1$, but for the sake of the uniquenes of the decimal representation $0.bar9$ is not a decimal representation of any number.
If you allow a "decimal representation" of a number to end finally with period $9$ as in $0.bar9$ or $1.123bar9$ this "decimal representation "of a number would not be unique.
We know by definition that $0.bar9=sum_{n=1}^{infty}(9/10)^n=1$, but for the sake of the uniquenes of the decimal representation $0.bar9$ is not a decimal representation of any number.
edited Nov 7 at 17:16
community wiki
2 revs
Michael Hoppe
add a comment |
add a comment |
up vote
-1
down vote
I can't help thinking that some of the people who aren't quite convinced by $0.33333 ... × 3$ might be happier considering multiples of $frac 19$ instead:
$frac{1}{9}=0.111111 . . .$
$frac{2}{9}=0.222222 . . .$
$frac{3}{9}=0.333333 . . .$
$frac{4}{9}=0.444444 . . .$
all the way up to
$frac{8}{9}=0.888888 . . .$
$frac{9}{9}=0.999999 . . .$
Somehow the consistent pattern helps. But there's still the psychological issue that because only finitely many digits are visible, 0.999999 . . . "feels smaller" than 1.000000 . . . while $frac 99$ doesn't.
add a comment |
up vote
-1
down vote
I can't help thinking that some of the people who aren't quite convinced by $0.33333 ... × 3$ might be happier considering multiples of $frac 19$ instead:
$frac{1}{9}=0.111111 . . .$
$frac{2}{9}=0.222222 . . .$
$frac{3}{9}=0.333333 . . .$
$frac{4}{9}=0.444444 . . .$
all the way up to
$frac{8}{9}=0.888888 . . .$
$frac{9}{9}=0.999999 . . .$
Somehow the consistent pattern helps. But there's still the psychological issue that because only finitely many digits are visible, 0.999999 . . . "feels smaller" than 1.000000 . . . while $frac 99$ doesn't.
add a comment |
up vote
-1
down vote
up vote
-1
down vote
I can't help thinking that some of the people who aren't quite convinced by $0.33333 ... × 3$ might be happier considering multiples of $frac 19$ instead:
$frac{1}{9}=0.111111 . . .$
$frac{2}{9}=0.222222 . . .$
$frac{3}{9}=0.333333 . . .$
$frac{4}{9}=0.444444 . . .$
all the way up to
$frac{8}{9}=0.888888 . . .$
$frac{9}{9}=0.999999 . . .$
Somehow the consistent pattern helps. But there's still the psychological issue that because only finitely many digits are visible, 0.999999 . . . "feels smaller" than 1.000000 . . . while $frac 99$ doesn't.
I can't help thinking that some of the people who aren't quite convinced by $0.33333 ... × 3$ might be happier considering multiples of $frac 19$ instead:
$frac{1}{9}=0.111111 . . .$
$frac{2}{9}=0.222222 . . .$
$frac{3}{9}=0.333333 . . .$
$frac{4}{9}=0.444444 . . .$
all the way up to
$frac{8}{9}=0.888888 . . .$
$frac{9}{9}=0.999999 . . .$
Somehow the consistent pattern helps. But there's still the psychological issue that because only finitely many digits are visible, 0.999999 . . . "feels smaller" than 1.000000 . . . while $frac 99$ doesn't.
answered Nov 27 at 22:36
community wiki
timtfj
add a comment |
add a comment |
protected by Alex Becker Mar 27 '14 at 2:58
Thank you for your interest in this question.
Because it has attracted low-quality or spam answers that had to be removed, posting an answer now requires 10 reputation on this site (the association bonus does not count).
Would you like to answer one of these unanswered questions instead?
27
Seriously people what's with all the duplicates? Check and see if someone has already given your answer first!
– Noah Snyder
Jul 20 '10 at 20:28
78
Let me say a word about why 1/3 = .33333... is not obvious at all. What does it mean to say that some number is 1/3? Well division is the operation that undoes multiplication, so it means that it's a number that when you multiply by 3 you get 1. Well what happens when you multiply .3333... times 3? You get .9999... So unless you already know that .99999...=1 then you can't prove that 1/3 = .3333... The fact that .9999...=1 is more basic than the fact that 1/3 = .33333....!
– Noah Snyder
Jul 20 '10 at 21:32
11
Between any two different numbers, there is always another number between them. there is no number between 0.999... and 1
– Joao
Apr 28 '14 at 3:07
4
New prospective answerers, please heed Noah Snyder's comment from over five years ago. It's all the more valuable now.
– Brian Tung
Jan 15 '16 at 23:12
2
@BT: yes, it is a real number, and the question is not meaningless nor stupid. The number $0.999cdots $ is a perfectly well-defined real number: $sum_{k=1}^infty frac9 {10^k}$. It just happens to be the real number that we usually call "one".
– Martin Argerami
Dec 15 '16 at 5:55